Overzichtsartikel Framing

download Overzichtsartikel Framing

of 21

Transcript of Overzichtsartikel Framing

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    1/21

    Frames revisitedthe coherence-inducingfunction of frames

    Monika A. Bednarek

    Department of English Linguistics, Augsburg University,Universitatsstrae 10, D-86135 Augsburg, Germany

    Received 20 September 2003; received in revised form 2 September 2004; accepted 19 September 2004

    Abstract

    The subject of this paper is the hearers1 application to discourse of frames mental knowledge

    structures that capture the typical features of a situation in order to secure coherence. Having

    established a working definition offrame, the paper will focus on the relation between text, context,

    world-knowledge and coherence. Different types of frames (linguistic as well as non-linguistic) andtheir coherence-inducing functions are discussed with reference to authentic examples. It is shown

    that the hearers (re-)constructed coherence of texts is the result of a complex interplay of linguistic

    (con)text and non-linguistic (frame) knowledge.

    # 2004 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

    Keywords: Discourse; Coherence; Cohesion; Frames; Scripts; Schemas

    1. Introduction: the relevance of frame theory in linguistics

    After the cognitive turn in the 1980s, modern linguistics has increasingly favored an

    approach to language that is based on our experience of the world and the way we perceive

    and conceptualize it, i.e. the cognitive linguistic approach (cf. Ungerer and Schmid, 1996:x).

    Some of the key concerns of this branch of linguistics are prototypes, categories, metaphors,

    metonymy, and the topic of this paper frames.

    Broadly speaking, frame theory deals with our knowledge of the world. In a first

    definition, a frame can be regarded as a mental knowledge structure which captures

    www.elsevier.com/locate/pragma

    Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705

    1 In this paper, hearer refers to hearer(s)/reader(s) and speaker refers to speaker(s)/writer(s).

    0378-2166/$ see front matter # 2004 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

    doi:10.1016/j.pragma.2004.09.007

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    2/21

    the typical features of the world. Ever since its introduction, the frame concept

    has interested researchers from various fields and backgrounds (cf. Tannen, 1993a: 3;

    1993b: 15). Pioneers came from philosophy and psychology (cf. Konerding, 1993: 8), but

    their concepts were developed and reinterpreted by researchers in artificial intelligence

    (Minsky, 1975, 1977), and sociology (Goffman, 1974, 1981) to name but a few fields and

    authors.2

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705686

    Fig. 1. Overview of the use of the term frame.

    2 For a discussion of a large number offields and authors, cf. Tannen (1993b: 15-21) and Konerding (1993: 20-

    77).

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    3/21

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 687

    Fig.

    2.

    Overview

    oflinguists

    terms.

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    4/21

    Despite the fact that there is no unifiedframe theory with specific terms and definitions,

    frame theory has also, in some way or other, gained widespread acceptance by linguists,

    who concentrate on various aspects of the frame phenomenon: Raskin (1984) and

    Konerding (1993), for instance, are interested in lexicography and the relation betweenframes and meaning. Indeed, frame semantics plays a major role in linguistic frame theory.

    The Round Table Discussion of frame semanticists (published in Quaderni di Semantica

    1985 and 1986) counts among its participants such leading researchers as Fillmore,

    Hudson, Raskin and Tannen (see e.g. Fillmore, 1985, 1986). The frame concept has also

    been applied in discourse analysis (e.g. Brown and Yule, 1983; Muller, 1984). Chafe (1977)

    is primarily concerned with frames and verbalization, i.e. those processes by which

    nonverbal knowledge is turned into language (Chafe, 1977: 41) and Shanon (1981) deals

    with linguistic indicators (Shanon, 1981: 35) of frames.

    Unfortunately, but maybe inevitably, the result of this has been a terminological

    confusion: frame became a term associated and linked with different, though related

    phenomena. At the same time, a range of other expressions (script, schema, scenario) were

    chosen to refer to these notions. Figs. 1 and 2 provide an overview of these developments.

    It seems to me as if the competing terms (scenario, schema, script) usually differ only in

    emphasis and cannot easily be distinguished, and that, considering the examples used in

    their elaboration, they may be seen as particular instances of frames. I will hence follow

    Fillmore in regarding frame as a general cover term for the set of concepts variously

    known, in the literature on natural language understanding, as schema, script,

    scenario, ideational scaffolding cognitive model, or folk theory (Fillmore, 1982:

    111).This paper is concerned with the relationship between frames and discourse, in

    particular, the coherence-inducing function of frames. It will be seen that the hearers

    application of frames is of crucial importance in enabling him/her to create coherence.

    Having established a working definition of frame, I will then outline the various ways in

    which such coherence-inducing frames may work in discourse.

    2. A working definition of frame

    Despite its roots in philosophy and psychology, frame theory is generally associatedwith Minskys work in artificial intelligence (AI). In his research, Minsky takes up a

    notion introduced by the psychologist Bartlett as early as 1932: [. . .] the past operates

    as an organised mass rather than as a group of elements each of which retains its

    specific character. (Bartlett, 1932: 197).3 Being a researcher in AI, Minsky is,

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705688

    3 It is indeed a bit surprising that most of the relevant linguistic literature refers to research undertaken in AI

    rather than to research undertaken in psychology and psycholinguistics (my thanks go to one of the reviewers of

    this article for pointing this out), although much experimental research in these areas has focused on the role of

    (schematic) knowledge in learning, understanding and remembering (Barsalou, 1992). Building on research by

    Bartlett (1932) and Piaget (1969) as well as AI research, such experiments (e.g. Bransford, 1979; Bransford and

    Johnson, 1973) often use linguistic data, and have shown how essential (frame) knowledge is to effective

    comprehension, inferencing, elaboration, construction, recall, indeed virtually every cognitive task (Barsalou,

    1992: 163).

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    5/21

    however, first and foremost concerned with the question of how to equip computers

    with the world knowledge they would need in order to perform certain otherwise

    impossible tasks. But he also claims to be interested in a theory of human thinking

    (Minsky, 1975: 215), and his definition of frames is now quite famous and anoften-cited reference in linguistics (e.g. Konerding, 1993: 24; Brown and Yule, 1983:

    238):

    Here is the essence of the frame theory: When one encounters a new situation [. . .],

    one selects from memory a structure called aframe. This is a remembered framework

    to be adapted to fit reality by changing details as necessary. A frame is a data-

    structure for representing a stereotyped situation like being in a certain kind of living

    room or going to a childs birthday party. Attached to each frame are several kinds of

    information. [. . .] Some is about what one can expect to happen next (Minsky,

    1977: 355).

    According to Minsky, then, a frame can be considered a mental representation of our

    knowledge of the world, a data-structure that is located in human memory and can be

    selected or retrieved when needed. A frame is thought of as a certain structure; it is a

    network of nodes and relations (Minsky, 1977: 355) which seem to be structured as

    different levels. There are the fixed top levels, representing those components of a

    situation that are always true, and there are the lower levels, which have many terminals,

    slots that must be filled by specific instances or data (Minsky, 1977: 355). Those

    specific instances, or assignments, can themselves be smaller sub-frames, and usually

    have to fulfill certain conditions given by the terminals through what Minsky callsmarkers. Concerning the terminals, Minsky highlights the fact that

    [a] frames terminals are normally already filled with default assignments. [. . .]

    The default assignments are attached loosely to their terminals, so that they can be

    easily displaced by new items that fit better the current situation. [. . .] Once a frame is

    proposed to represent a situation, a matching process tries to assign values to each

    frames terminals, consistent with the markers at each place (Minsky, 1977: 356,

    original emphasis).

    Apparently, some of these assignments are mandatory, others optional (Minsky,

    1975: 239). Basically, this means that in our memory, knowledge is stored in a verylarge number of frames and frame-systems (collections of related frames, Minsky,

    1977: 355). For instance, we might possess something like a [BED-ROOM]4 frame, a

    [HOSPITAL] frame, a [SCHOOL] frame and so on, each of which is comprised of certain

    typical features such as BED, LAMP, BED-SIDE TABLE, etc. in the case of the [BED-ROOM]

    frame. When we encounter a new situation (e.g. on entering a particular bed-room), a

    selecting and matching process begins: first, a frame is evoked on the basis of partial

    evidence or expectation (Minsky, 1977: 359). Then, we compare the new experience

    (the particular bed-room) to this selected frame ([BED-ROOM]) and finally, we assign

    features of this new experience (a particular bed, lamp, bed-side table, etc.) to the

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 689

    4 Following Ungerer and Schmid, frames will be indicated typographically by small capitals in brackets.

    Frame features or cognitive categories will be indicated by small caps only (Ungerer and Schmid, 1996: 206).

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    6/21

    frames terminals (depending on whether the features satisfy the conditions governing

    their assignments).

    One of the problems with Minskys frame theory is its fuzziness. That is to say, most of

    the time, he relies on the power of his hypotheses as well as on the readers power ofimagining the cognitive actions he proposes. As Minsky himself admits, his theory is

    incomplete and fragmented:

    [t]he schemes proposed herein are incomplete in many respects. First, I often

    propose representations without specifying the processes that will use them.

    Sometimes I only describe properties the structures should exhibit. I talk about

    markers and assignments as though it were obvious how they are attached and linked;

    it is not (Minsky, 1975: 213).

    Despite its shortcomings, however, Minskys frame concept remains a helpful one, if its

    specifics are disregarded. On the whole, a frame concept derived from the one Minsky

    developed helps explain a number of linguistic phenomena and proves a useful tool in

    discourse analysis.

    As mentioned above, Minsky considered a frame a cognitive phenomenon, a structure

    that is stored in the mind. In linguistics, it was at first regarded as a linguistic concept by

    Fillmore, but experienced a cognitive reinterpretation in the course of the years; nowadays,

    most linguists agree in their definition offrame as a mental phenomenon, as a knowledge

    structure (e.g. Yule, 1996: 85, Tannen and Wallat, 1993: 60, Stubbs, 2001: 3). Such

    knowledge structures are not innate but acquired through socialization, constructed out of

    experience (out of our own experience or accounts of experiences by others etc.), and arehence both diachronically and culturally dependent. The importance of cultural

    dependency has been shown by Tannen (1993b) and Yule (1996: 87); as to diachronic

    dependency, it is one of the logical consequences of socialization (e.g., before the invention

    of the computer and other technical innovations, people did not possess any associated

    frames). Once established, frames are rather stable (cf. Stubbs, 2001: 5), with some frames

    seeming more stable than others, i.e. not as prone to change. It seems probable that such

    stable frames usually concern situations or objects which have exhibited the same features

    for centuries and are unlikely to change in the near future, for instance a [ BED-ROOM] frame.

    Other frames, dealing with more fluid situations or concepts (for example role-related

    frames) are more likely to change.Socialization is always both individual and social. We experience life individually

    and subjectively, but we also possess certain innate perception patterns that we use to

    interpret the world, and we have more or less the same social experiences depending on

    our respective culture (cf. Muller, 1984: 57). Inasmuch as they are relevant to

    communication, frames appear to be conventionalized and capture the prototypical

    features of a situation.5

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705690

    5 This does not mean that frames may not additionally include idiosyncratic features, but that these are, in

    general, irrelevant to communication. This has been emphasized by Clark (1978), who argues that hearers, on

    hearing an utterance such as hes crazy, may indeed associate this utterance with the fact that they have a mad

    Uncle Harry. But, he says, they set aside this association, knowing that it cannot be relevant as far as the speakers

    original intention is concerned. This suggests that the hearers idiosyncratic properties of frames are not usually

    called up for the interpretation of the discourse at hand.

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    7/21

    As far as the structure of frames is concerned, there is hardly any linguistic evidence for

    frame structure (and no simple way to observe frame structure in detail). This is probably

    why linguists often do not touch this matter and if they do, they usually refer back to

    Minskys frame structure (e.g. Brown and Yule, 1983: 239). Ungerer and Schmid (1996:212 f.) see a frame as being constructed out of categories and their specific

    interrelations (e.g. X has a Y, X is on Y, X is a part of Y); the categories provide default

    assignments (by supplying prototypes) and associated expectations. It does seem

    reasonable to adopt such a more general view, since we cannot directly observe the

    structure of frames.6

    Some of the features/components in a frame seem to be more central to a frame than

    others. In a [BED-ROOM] frame, for example, one would always expect something like a

    bed. This would only change in the unlikely case that reality as we know it, has become

    radically altered (for example, if no more beds could be found in bedrooms because

    everyone sleeps on the floor). The BED feature seems to be a feature which is very central

    to the [BED-ROOM] frame and associated expectations are very high. In contrast, other

    features of the frame such as TV, or MIRROR, might not necessarily be expected in a

    bedroom, but are still considered part of the frame. Minsky differentiates between

    obligatory and optional features (cf. Minsky, 1975: 239), but I would prefer to speak of

    central and peripheral features, the features being situated on a scale, simply because it

    is not easy to discover which features are really obligatory: a bedroom, for example,

    might still be considered a bedroom, even if there is no bed in it (e.g., when someone has

    just moved in and sleeps on the floor); in this case, the function of a bed-room is the

    central feature.Quite often, a feature is itself a sub-frame. Consider the [ FLYING ON A PLANE] frame,

    which consists, according to Ungerer and Schmid (1996: 212), of various components such

    as PILOT, FLIGHT ATTENDANT, LIFE VEST etc., as well as of sub-frames which stand for more

    specific situations of a flight, e.g. [EATING], [WATCHING THE MOVIE] and [GOING TO THE TOILET].

    This would be a (static) default hierarchy.

    It is also possible to classify frames in different ways. Frames differ greatly in respect to

    complexity and specificity: they have more general and more specific forms (going on

    holiday versus going on a cheap last-minute package holiday to Spain). (Stubbs, 2001: 5).

    Moreover, Tannen distinguishes between frames that refer to events ([PERSONAL ENCOUNTERS],

    [CONFRONTATION], [ACCIDENT], [THEFT]) and those that refer to objects ([PEAR TREE], [ROAD])(Tannen, 1993b: 35ff.). Probably, frames can also refer to persons, actions, places, types,

    roles etc. Scripts or scenarios are, of course, also terms for frames which refer to events (see

    above).

    To sum up, in my working definition (derived from Minskys and Ungerer and

    Schmids), aframe consists ofcognitive features/components and their relations. A feature/

    component can itself be a sub-frame. The features seem to exist on a scale ranging from

    central to peripheral and provide default assumptions by supplying prototypes. Associated

    expectations are higher with regards to central features than with regards to peripheral

    features: if a feature is central to a frame, a speaker will most certainly expect an actual

    instance of this feature when its respective frame is activated.

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 691

    6 However, instead of categories, I shall speak of frame features or components.

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    8/21

    3. Frames and coherence

    The effort to establish a working definition of frame has shown that there are certain

    drawbacks and shortcomings regarding frame theory (in particular, that the nature offrames must remain highly speculative). Yet, as will be seen in the following, its

    application provides an interesting angle on the relation between text, context, world

    knowledge, and coherence.

    Like the frame concept, coherence is a rather fuzzy notion in linguistics and there is as

    yet no generally accepted definition or theory of coherence (cf. Bublitz, 1999:1). Here, I

    shall not discuss the notion in detail, but will restrict myself to some observations

    concerning the difference between cohesion and coherence. Cohesion is a property of texts

    and refers to the linguistic means that provide texture (i.e., link the sentences of a text),

    such as Halliday and Hasans (1976) reference, substitution, ellipsis, reiteration,

    collocation and conjunction, Hoeys (1991) patterns of lexis, etc. Coherence, on the

    other hand is best described as the semantic, logical, or cognitive connections that underlie

    a text (cf. de Beaugrande and Dressler, 1981: 4; Bussmann, 1996: 80; Thompson and Zhou,

    2000: 121). Rather than assuming that these connections exist independently of the speaker

    or hearer, coherence is nowadays clearly defined in relation to the hearers contribution:

    [. . .] coherence is only measurable in terms of a readers assessment (Hoey, 1991: 11).

    Thus, we may come up with a simple distinction between coherence and cohesion:

    coherence is not a text-inherent property; it concerns the logical relations in a given text

    which are established by hearers. In other words, it refers to the extent to which hearers find

    that this text holds together and constitutes a unified whole. Cohesion, on the other hand,is a text-inherent property; it concerns the explicit textual means by which potential logical

    connections are signaled. In other words, it refers to the way in which sentences are

    connected in a text by lexical and structural means (cf. also Bublitz, 1999).

    Thus, I shall assume that it is the hearers who establish coherence, and not the texts,

    although the cohesive means of texts play a large role in helping hearers to establish

    coherence. In general, we operate on a default principle of coherence (cf. Brown and Yule,

    1983: 66 f.; Bublitz and Lenk, 1999: 156 f.), assuming that a text is coherent (and that the

    speaker adheres to the principles of cooperation (Grice, 1975) that are taken for granted in

    conversation). This is why we go to great lengths in order to create coherence, drawing on

    all possible cues. Consider (1), which I have taken from Vuchinich (1977):

    (1)

    S: Well unless youre not a member; if yer a member of TM h=TranscendentalMeditationi people do, ah simply because its such a fucking high priceto get in there (1,0 sec) its like thirty five dollars

    C: its like water polo

    (2,0 sec)

    S: Why, is it expensive

    (Vuchinich, 1977: 246)

    In this example, Ss assumption of coherence leads him/her to interpret Cs remarkits

    like water polo as relevant and coherent, although, in fact, C wanted to test the reaction of

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705692

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    9/21

    his partner by deliberately uttering a non-coherent utterance (cf. Vuchinich, 1977: 235).

    Thus, S tries to look for a way to make sense of this comparison, coming up with the most

    likely explanation, namely that TM is like water polo because both are expensive. One

    might argue that S takes into account two frames here: the established [TRANSCENDENTAL

    MEDITATION] discourse frame with an emphasis on the feature EXPENSIVE and a default [WATER

    POLO] frame. Induced by Cs statement, S tries to establish an analogy between these two

    frames on the basis of the prominent feature EXPENSIVE. However, as his/her default [WATER

    POLO] frame does not automatically include the feature EXPENSIVE, and because s/he is not

    certain of this [WATER POLO] frame, i.e. s/he is not certain of the fact that EXPENSIVE is not

    included in WATER POLO, s/he has to question C about it.7

    In the following sections, I shall give some more examples in which hearers resort to

    frames in order to establish coherence. It has been shown that frame breaks may cause

    misunderstanding (Falkner, 1997: 115117), a disturbance in communication, or more

    precisely, disturbed coherence (Bublitz and Lenk, 1999: 162 f.; 170 f.). The emphasis in

    this paper, however, will be placed on the way in which hearers apply a certain frame to a

    piece of text in order to create coherence, and on which grounds they do so. In this respect, I

    will discuss both frames about non-linguistic phenomena in the world and frames about

    language and communication. It is especially the latter that are often neglected in linguistic

    research on frames.

    3.1. Specialized frames: [RUGBY], [CRICKET]

    It is quite obvious that our frames for non-linguistic phenomena in the worldcontribute much to the coherence of discourse. This is also the reason that frame-

    conflicts trigger lengthy explanations and cause contradictions or questions

    (Tannen, 1993b; Tannen and Wallat, 1993). The importance of frames for understanding

    a text becomes more than obvious in examples of highly specialized language use, such

    as in (2):

    (2)

    Rugby

    [...]The world champions [Australia] outscored the Maori in Saturday [...] five tries

    to two but did not seal victory until replacement winger Graeme Bond went over toscore right on fulltime. [...] The Wallabies looked to have the match under control

    when Larkham intercepted a loose pass from replacement David Hill and sprinted

    half the length of the field to score untouched and give his side a 31-19 lead with 15

    minutes to go. But the Maori pulled back to within two points with less than five

    minutes to go with Spencers try and two penalties from Hill. [...]Walker went past

    four defenders to score a wonderful solo try.

    This example shows the significance of the existence of specialized frames in the

    hearers mind. In (2), rugby induces the hearer to apply his/her [RUGBY] frame to the

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 693

    7 A speaker certain of his/her [WATER POLO] frame, because s/he is, for instance, active in this sport, might have

    answered something like Why, water polo isnt expensive instead.

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    10/21

    text, and there are manifold expressions in the text which relate to this frame, for

    instance five tries to two, replacement winger, to score right on fulltime, intercepted a

    loose pass, to score untouched, to score a wonderful solo try, and so on. As Brown and

    Yule point out, unless the reader has specialized knowledge about the [mentioned]entity [...], this type of expression will create a potential discontinuity in the reader s

    interpretation and require inferencing. (1983: 267). The text itself guides the hearer to

    make certain inferences about the actions and entities in question. Thus, the hearer may

    assume that five tries are better than two, that to score untouched is a good thing, that in

    rugby you score a try etc. The hearer might, in addition, apply related [SPORT] frames to

    the text; in this case, linguistic expressions such as penalty and score may be

    interpreted in reference to known frames with which they are also associated. Penalty

    would then be seen as something negative, score as something positive, a desired goal

    of the game. Hearers will generally try to establish coherence in this text both through

    the text and through the application of other, related frames. In (3), this seems much

    more difficult because of the high frequency of expressions which do not allow the

    application of related frames, so that hearers have to rely on the context alone to infer

    meaning.

    (3)

    Cricket

    [...] But Australia set off in hot pursuit and were barely put out of their stride when

    Shoaib did Adam Gilchrist for pace with a ball which bowled the wicketkeeper-

    batsman between bat and pad from round the wicket. (http://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/4/buk19/html)

    In both (2) and (3), readers with the respective [RUGBY] and [CRICKET] frame, however,

    would not have any difficulty in creating a perfectly understandable and coherent

    interpretation of these texts. They would know for instance, that in (2) a try refers to the

    games GOAL of getting the ball over the line at the end of the playing-field and touching

    it down without being touched and that you SCORE 5 POINTS by doing so. They would

    know wingers are players whose position is on the side of the pitch, that fulltime refers to

    the END OF THE GAME and that scoring untouched means that no one even tackled the

    player, whereas a solo try refers to a player not passing the ball to anyone else in scoring.Readers with the relevant background would also apply their frame knowledge about

    [CRICKET] to (3), i.e. that there are two TEAMS (of 11 men), who are alternatively BATTERS

    and FIELDERS. They would know that when it is a teams turn to bat, two batsmen go in the

    field and try to hit the CRICKET BALL as far as possible and get as many RUNS as possible

    (by running the 22 yards between the two wickets (a set of three stumps topped by a pair

    of bails)), while the fielders try to catch the ball. And that the BOWLERS GOAL is to hit the

    wicket, while the wicketkeeper (who squats behind the wicket) tries to catch the ball to

    get the batsman out. They would hence know the significance of what is described in

    the text: the bowler (Shoaib) bowled a very fast ball which was too fast for the batsman

    ( Adam Gilchrist) to play against (did [him] for pace), and which went between his batand his pad (the wooden club and protective clothing for his legs with which he defends

    his wicket). This ball was delivered by Shoaib with his non-bowling arm closest to the

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705694

    http://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/4/buk19/htmlhttp://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/4/buk19/htmlhttp://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/4/buk19/htmlhttp://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/4/buk19/html
  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    11/21

    wicket (from round the wicket) and bowled Gilchrist (hit his stumps causing him to lose

    his wicket).8

    While examples like these are full of specialized language use, more generally (as

    confirmed by the findings ofTannen and Wallat, 1993) frame-conflicts are a considerablesource of disturbed coherence, and are responsible for translation problems as well as

    cross-cultural misunderstandings. There seems to be an interaction between frame

    instigating words and expressions (which guide the application of a certain frame to a given

    piece of discourse), the frames existing in a hearers mind, and the creation of coherence.

    3.2. Frames about communication

    Frames about non-linguistic phenomena are not the only type of frames that contribute

    to coherence; frames about communication, too, may create coherence. In the following, I

    shall look at the establishment of coherence through communicative frames for texttypes, genres, and communicative principles.

    3.2.1. Frames about communication I: [TEXT TYPES], [GENRES]

    [TEXT TYPE/GENRE] frames may play a certain role in creating coherence, for instance

    where literature is concerned. Here is an example from a contemporary text (text source

    follows at later point).

    (4)

    [Mrs. and Mr. Smith discuss the death of Bobby Watson]

    Mrs. Smith No, its his wife Im thinking of. She was called Bobby. Like

    him, Bobby Watson. Since they had the same name, one could not distinguishbetween them when one saw them together. Only after his death could one really

    know who was the one and who was the other. Still, even today there are people

    who mix her up with the deceased and offer her their condolences. You know her?

    Mr. Smith. Ive only seen her once, by chance, at Bobbys funeral.

    Mrs. Smith. Ive never seen her. Is she beautiful?

    Mr. Smith. She has regular facial features and yet one cannot say she s beautiful.

    She is too tall and too big. Her features are not regular and still one can say that

    she is very beautiful. She is a bit too short and too thin. She is a voice teacher.

    [. . .]

    Mrs. Smith. And when are the two planning to get married?

    For any reader who approaches this text without any prior information, this extract

    certainly seems incoherent and absurd, being full of contradictions and frame-breaks.

    There do not seem to be any linguistic cues in the text that automatically would evoke a

    frame in which this piece of discourse was coherent. Most of the time, however, readers

    know in advance what type of text they are dealing with: a newspaper article, an 18th

    century novel, a poem, a contemporary novel, a drama etc., and thus, the respective frame is

    evoked simply because of the situation.9 Now, if a reader knows that what s/he is dealing

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 695

    8 I would like to thank David Oakey for his help with these examples.9 There may also be features in the text typical of a certain genre and allowing hearers to identify it as such, but

    often readers know from the beginning what they are dealing with and they expect a piece of discourse consistent

    with their frame for the text type/genre in question.

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    12/21

    with in (4) is indeed an extract from Ionescos La Cantatrice Chauve (Ionesco,

    1984: 11; my translation, MB), a piece of absurd theater, s/he may find it in a way

    coherent within this frame. The application of an [ABSURD THEATER] frame may render

    the text coherent because that frame includes features such as ABSURDITY OF LIFE,INSURMOUNTABLE DIFFERENCES BETWEEN SIGNIFIE AND SIGNIFIANT, or INSUFFICIENCY OF

    LANGUAGE.10

    3.2.2. Frames about communication II: [JOKE]

    Example (4) has already shown how [TEXT TYPE/GENRE] frames can be applied by hearers

    to establish at least some degree of coherence for an otherwise completely incoherent piece

    of discourse. A similar, if slightly different example is (5):

    (5)

    Jacob: Theres a guy driving his car down the road, okay? Hewas driving along. And hes

    driving a nineteen-fifty-seven convertible, T-bird. And he sees uh Jay Leno

    jogging along the side of the road. And he goes, I hate talk show hosts. He

    swerves over and he runs him over, kills him. And hes driving, and he turns a

    corner, driving down the road a bit. And he sees ah ah JohnnyCarson. And he says,

    God, I hate talk show hosts. He swerves over and he kills him. Then he- then

    he sees the uh his ministerhitchhiking on the side of the road. {tsk} And he stops

    and he says, Hows it going father, do you need a ride? Hes like Yes, my son,

    yes, could you take me to the uh church? And they start driving along he sees

    Oprah Winfrey driving along- yknow jogging along on the side of the road. Andhe goes, God, I hate talk show hosts, but Ive got a minister here, its kind of risky

    to swerve over and kill her, yknow? {tsk} So he goes, Heres what Ill do: Ill

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705696

    10 Here is the original French text:

    Mme Smith. Non, cest a sa femme que je pense. Elle sappelait comme lui, Bobby, Bobby Watson. Comme

    ils avaient le meme nom, on ne pouvait pas les distinguer lun de lautre quand on les voyait

    ensemble. Ce nest quapres sa mort a lui, quon a pu vraiment savoir qui etait lun et qui etait

    lautre. Pourtant, aujourdhui encore, il y a des gens qui la confondent avec le mort et luipresentent des condoleances. Tu la connais?

    M. Smith. Je ne lai vue quune fois, par hasard, a lenterrenment de Bobby.

    Mme Smith. Je ne lai jamais vue. Est-ce quelle est belle?

    M. Smith. Elle a des traits reguliers et pourtant on ne peut pas dire quelle est belle. Elle est trop grande et

    trop forte. Ses traits ne sont pas reguliers et pourtant on peut dire quelle est tres belle. Elle est un

    peu trop petite et trop maigre. Elle est professeur de chant.

    [...]

    Mme Smith. Et quand pensent-ils se marier, tous les deux?

    The early criticism, or misunderstanding of Ionescos play is equally explicable by frame-theory. People did not

    yet possess an [ABSURD THEATER] frame, only a [DRAMA] frame which they applied to the piece. Because of

    what they saw on stage was not included in their frame, they could not make any sense of the play; in a way, this

    was a case of disturbed coherence. (This also applies to other forms of art, for instance abstract art, or performance

    art.)

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    13/21

    pretend like I uh I sneeze and Ill swerve by mistake. So he is driving along.

    When she comes up, he sort of sneezes, and he swerves over, and he has his eyes

    closed, and he goes, Oh, myGod, I heard a thud. Did I hit her? And the minister

    goes, No, you missed her, but I got her with the car door.

    Erik: Hehheh.

    Jacob: I got a laugh.

    (SBCCN: Two jokes, my emphasis)

    In (5), there is a clear instance of a frame-break which could supposedly lead to

    disturbed coherence. Ministerevokes a default [MINISTER] frame in the hearer which should

    include such features as PEACEFUL, LAW-ABIDING, NOT AGGRESSIVE etc. Thus, the fact that the

    minister actually kills someone and the way he talks about it present clear frame-breaks. But

    this does not lead to disturbed coherence, or indeed any miscommunication because of thesuperordinate [JOKE] frame which is applied to this piece of discourse. In jokes, things do not

    have to be probable, or realistic, nor do they have to conform to our knowledge of what

    things typically are like in the world. Indeed, frame-breaks are an important feature in jokes,

    and they often give rise to humorous effects. This becomes quite clear in the following

    example:

    (6):

    Ralph: You ever hear that joke?

    Mary: No. {laughing}

    Ralph: Well, it was just one woman wanted a telegram? She always wanted asinging telegram? Guy says, Maam I dont think you want this as a singing

    telegram. Yeah, go ahead. Fred and the kids are dead. {singing and

    clapping}

    Mary: {laughs briefly} I didnt get it.

    Ralph: You dont get it. You dont sing a telegram about death or anything bad

    news.

    (SBCCN: Singing Telegram, my emphasis)

    To explain why the joke is funny, Ralph simply resorts to stating the frame-

    break: You dont sing a telegram about death or anything bad news. The frame-break

    may thus be seen as the very cause of laughter, the essence of the joke in this case as well as

    in (5). The application of the [JOKE] frame by the hearer to both (5) and (6) leads to

    unproblematic coherence of both pieces of discourse. In contrast to (4), theIonesco example,

    [JOKE] frames are usually triggered by the text. In all of the SBCCN examples of jokes,

    the [JOKE] frame was either triggered by the context (i.e. people were talking about jokes

    in general and then told a joke), or, more often, by introductory remarks by the speaker such

    as:

    You know that joke?

    Have you heard the drunken Irishman one?/You ever hear that joke? Did I tell you my lumber joke?

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 697

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    14/21

    Didnt you tell the one about the the guy in the bar who who suddenly uh startshearing these very nice things said about him?

    Ivegot a joke for you./Ive got a pretty apretty topical joke, pretty uh current joke, pretty

    important joke for the country to hear.11

    With these introductions, speakers successfully guide hearers creation of coherence and

    help them to apply the right frame to what follows.

    3.2.3. Frames about communication III: communicative principles

    Other frequent instances of the way in which frames about language help to establish

    coherence are found in [COMMUNICATION] frames. These seem to be particularly called for

    whenever no explicit cohesive means are present in the text. This is the case in the much

    quoted example (7):

    (7)

    A: Theres the doorbell.

    B: Im in the bath.

    (Brown and Yule, 1983: 196)

    as well as in the following example:

    (8)

    A: Wheres Bill?

    B: Theres a yellow VW outside Sues house.

    (Levinson, 1983: 192).

    In both cases, one might argue that the first pair part of the exchange opens a frame

    which allows to treat the second pair part as an answer. Apart from the application of what

    one might term a [QUESTION] frame, other communicative principles may also play a part in

    the coherent interpretation of these utterances. However, because communicative

    principles/maxims have been treated so extensively in pragmatics I shall not discuss

    them further in this section. Moreover, it seems as if texts which exhibit no cohesion

    whatsoever are relatively rare (Bublitz and Lenk, 1999: 165).

    3.3. Reference resolution

    So far, we have seen how the application of linguistic and non-linguistic frames

    may help hearers to establish the overall coherence of texts. The focus will now

    be on the hearers application of frames in order to identify the referents of

    referring expressions. As Bublitz and Lenk (1999: 165) point out, unclear reference

    can lead to different degrees of disturbed coherence. Conversely, resorting to frames

    for reference resolution may be regarded as a special case of establishing coherence.

    In the following, I shall discuss the identification of referents of NPs with

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705698

    11 All examples are taken from the SBCCN (now called the SCoSE, Saarbru cken Corpus of Spoken English).

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    15/21

    de finite/indefinite articles, pronouns, and vague category identifiers (Channell,

    1994:128).

    3.3.1. Reference resolution I: definite/indefinite article

    One of the most important aspects of how frames contribute to coherence is the

    way they help the hearer to understand the reference of items introduced by a definite

    article. Frames help to create coherence by allowing the hearer to identify the correct

    (intended) referent of both definite and indefinite NPs, as seen in the following extract

    (definite NP):

    (9)

    He slammed the door of his building behind him; in wet weather, the lock tended to

    stick, and only violence would get the massive door to close or open. He shook his

    umbrella a few times, then furled it and stuck it under his arm. With his right hand,

    he grabbed the handrail and began the long climb to their apartment.

    (Donna Leon, Acqua Alta, 207, my emphasis)

    In this example, both the lock and the handrail are definite NPs whose interpreta-

    tion depends on frame-knowledge. The use of the definite article here does not correspond

    to its three basic functions usually described in traditional grammars (e.g. Quirk et al.,

    1973: 72 f.):

    It does not presuppose an earlier mention of the item introduced by the de finite articlesuch as in He saw a man on the street . . . The man wore a dark coat.

    There is no postmodification specifying the referent such as in He slammed the door ofhis building behind him.

    The item introduced is not unique such as in the sun, the moon, the stars.12

    Frame theory, however, may explain this specific use of the definite article quite clearly.

    One might argue that the door of his building opens up two frames: a [DOOR] frame and a

    [BUILDING] frame, with the [DOOR] frame probably constituting a sub-frame to the supe-

    rordinate [BUILDING] frame. The [DOOR] frame allows the hearer to take for granted several

    likely features of the frame: that a door may be opened, that you enter or exit a building/aroom through a door, that a door has a handle, that a door has a lock, and so on. Similarly,

    the [BUILDING] frame might include such features as PLACE WHERE PEOPLE LIVE, PLACE IN WHICH

    APARTMENTS MAY BE SITUATED, and the sub-frame [STAIRS] comprising the likely existence of a

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 699

    12 The use of the definite article may be closely related, however, to one case of specific reference mentioned by

    Quirk and Greenbaum only in passing:

    Even more covert are the presuppositions which permit the definite article in examples like the following:

    John asked his wife to put on the kettle while he looked in the paper to see what was on the radio.

    No prior mention ofa kettle, a paper, a radio is needed, since these things are part of the cultural situation (Quirk

    et al., 1973: 73; original emphasis).

    As in this constructed example, in (9) also, the lockand the handrail may, broadly speaking, be said to be part of

    the cultural situation, but I feel it is more fruitful to analyse these NPs in terms of frame theory.

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    16/21

    HANDRAIL. This is why the hearer will have no problems to understand the first reference to

    the lock and to the handrail, even though there is no antecedent. The hearer simply takes

    the speakers instructions (the use of a frame-instigating expression) and infers an

    interpretative frame to which to relate the following text.13 Thus, frame-instigatingexpressions/frame key-words and their associated default frames help the hearer to

    understand discourse, in other words, to create coherence.

    Indefinite NPs may sometimes also be employed with specific reference. Indeed, it is a

    well-known property of indefinite NPs such as the one in the much quoted example, Hes

    going to marry a Norwegian, that the NP may be used both with specific reference

    (referring to a specific Norwegian) and with generic reference, (referring to any Norwegian

    in general). This potential ambiguity is, however, usually resolved in discourse. Consider

    now the following example:

    (10)

    It is strange that the present centurys greatest hero is likely to remain Winston

    Churchill. For much of his life, respectable people regarded him as a reckless

    adventurer. As a wartime leader, he was accused of terrible crimes, and of

    mistakes which cost the nation dear. [...]

    That Churchill should continue to symbolise the defence of freedom is partly

    because of a coincidence in timing. [...]

    Reading Martin Gilberts spare, lucid and sensitive biography, Churchill: A life,

    one is reminded yet again of Churchills messiah-like quality arriving, God-given,

    in the nick of time to raise the spirits of those who still believed in a political systemwhich had everywhere been reviled, corrupted and duped by the totalitarians. [...]

    Of Hitler and even Roosevelt there have been revisionist accounts a-plenty, but

    attempts to replace the propaganda newsreel images of Churchill have so far

    been rare and unconvincing.

    That Gilberts account of Churchill, the product of more than three decades of

    meticulous research, reinforces the classic versions is probably inevitable. [...] Gilbert

    makes no apology for being the official biographer par excellence, and as

    such he has performed an inestimable service. The author tells the famous

    story of how Parliament misguidedly expressed its gratitude to an ageing

    premier by commissioning Graham Sutherland to paint his portrait with a resultso brutally candid that Clementine ordered its destruction.

    (Ben Pimlett on: Churchill: A Life, by Martin Gilbert, The Guardian Weekly,

    21 April 1991, my emphasis)

    In the above extract, an ageing premier has a specific reference: Winston Churchill;

    however, establishing this reference, or coherence, seems to be rather complex. On the one

    hand, an ageing premier is used anaphorically, referring back to Churchill. On the other

    hand, a) it does not refer back to the same Winston Churchill as in the previous text, but to

    a Winston Churchill at a certain period of his life, and b) there is no mention in the text

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705700

    13 Quirk et al. (1985: 267ff) explain this use of the definite article by reference to general knowledge and

    ellipsis, but also note that this explanation does not [. . .] apply to all such cases (Quirk et al., 1985: 268).

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    17/21

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    18/21

    of coherence, together with what seems a deviation from the norm of gender agreement in

    co-reference, which prompts the hearers inferences and his/her creation of coherence.

    In other instances of pronoun use, too, no direct antecedent nominal exists in the text;

    but here, the text instigates a frame in the hearer which, in turn, provides the basis fordetermining the intended referent of the pronoun. The use of the pronoun she in the

    following example provides an example:

    (12)

    [Talking about the First World War]

    I used to go about with a chap I dont know whether hes still alive now or not but

    there was nine ten eleven in the family altogether two girls and nine boys

    and she lost eight sons one after the other

    (Brown and Yule, 1983: 218)

    Brown and Yule point out, there is no linguistic expression which could be treated as the

    direct antecedent for she (Brown and Yule, 1983: 218). However, this is not a case of

    exophoric reference in the way Halliday and Hasan (1976: 32 ff.) understand the concept: the

    pronoun does not refer to the context of situation. But neither can it be said to be strictly

    anaphoric, referring to another item within the text (Halliday and Hasan, 1976: 32).

    Instead, she relates to a frame feature. The key-word family seems to trigger a [FAMILY] frame

    and, together with the mentioning of another frame element, namely SONS, permits the hearer

    to treat she as referring to the frame element MOTHER. Ina broader sense, thisuseof the pronoun

    is anaphoric, because the preceding text is the source of the evocation of the frame.

    16

    Thus, itdoes relate to the text as well as to the frame. Linguistic cues given by the speaker are the

    reason for the application of a certain frame by the hearer; without these cues and their

    associated frame, the hearer could neither identify the referent nor create coherence.

    3.3.3. Reference resolution III: Vague category identifiers

    Frames may also be applied in order to help hearers identify the referents introduced by

    vague category identifiers, i.e. structures consisting of exemplars of categories and tags

    such as or something/anything, and things, and things like that, and that(Channell, 1994:

    131), for instance:

    (13)

    There was no kind of social contact there was no coffee room or anything (Channell,

    1994: 119).

    The function of such structures is to direct[. . .] the hearer to access a set, of which the

    given item is a member whose characteristics will enable the hearer to identify the set

    (Channell, 1994: 122). Channell has carried out tests with native speaker respondents in

    order to find out how hearers identify the respective category of such vague expressions and

    points out that both linguistic and world knowledge are drawn upon in reference resolution.

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705702

    16 Schwarz calls this type of anaphor-antecedent relation indirect anaphors (Schwarz, 1997: 449 f.). Compare

    also Quirk et al., 1985: 267ff).

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    19/21

    For instance, for the test sentence She said they eat rice and that, didnt she, one respondent

    called up the following categories:

    Respondent a.vegetarian context: rice, beans, dried vegetables

    Chinese context: rice, chicken, green vegetables, sweet and sour

    Greek context: stuffed pepper, pilaf

    (Channell, 1994: 127)

    What is called context here could equally well be called frame. Frame theory would

    then suggest that such vague category identifiers in fact call up associated frames (rice

    could be associated with a [VEGETARIAN FOOD] frame, a [CHINESE FOOD] frame or a [GREEK

    FOOD] frame) and that these frames alongside other information (e.g. that Chinese food is

    eaten with chopsticks) include information about typical foods involved, which enables

    hearers to identify the relevant category.

    One might argue that some sort of bottom-up top-down interaction is involved: eat rice

    and thatactivates a [CHINESE/VEGETARIAN/GREEK FOOD] frame, but the context instantiates only

    oneof itsframe features(the category TYPICAL CHINESE/VEGETARIAN/GREEK FOODS) theonethatis

    necessaryfor theidentification of the referent (otherpossible frame features being, e.g., [EATING

    WITH CHOPSTICKS], [PREPARING CHINESE FOOD], [CHINESE RESTAURANT]). Other frame features are

    activated, but not instantiated by the sentence, though they might be by additional discourse

    (e.g. if the sentence above were followed by So, theyve got a wok, chopsticks and thator Oh, I

    hate eating with chopsticks). The problem with the sentence above is that the respondentdoes not know who they are, what preceded the sentence, and so on. Because the example

    sentence does not give any additional information concerning which frame is involved, the

    respondent comes up with the typical (zero-context, default) frames with which eating rice is

    associated ([VEGETARIAN FOOD], [CHINESE FOOD], [GREEK FOOD]). Naturally, in a real conversation.

    sentences are not uttered out of context and there will be many cues which help hearers to

    guess which specific frame is involved. Thus, the only way to find out more about how frames

    are activated is to look at utterances in a wider context. It is also necessary to explore in more

    detail the relationship between frames, superordinate categories, and (proto)typicality.

    4. Conclusion

    Frames are indeed an important factor for the creation of coherence by hearers. Frame-

    conflicts may lead to disturbed coherence, although they need not necessarily do so: the

    application of a superordinate frame may override deviations from the norm and thus create

    coherence. The examples given above have strengthened my assumption that coherence is

    indeed based on cohesion (if we consider the lexical items, expressions, and phrases that

    activate frames as cohesive devices). In almost all of the texts, frames were triggered in the

    hearer through the text. Even in cases such as [TEXT TYPE] frames, one might argue that

    certain topoi17

    would lead the hearer to infer the correct interpretative frame even if s/he

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 703

    17 Such as the list of the cast given at the beginning of a play, the text alignment of poems, etc.

  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    20/21

    came to the text without prior knowledge or expectations. Decoding and inferring thus

    seem, in fact, to be complementary actions (Bublitz, 2001: 7) helping the hearer to

    understand a given text.

    References

    Ionesco, Eugene, 1984. La Cantatrice Chauve. Reclam, Stuttgart. [text first published in 1954].

    Leon, Donna, 1997. Acqua Alta. Pan, London.

    Pimlett, Ben, 1991. Churchill: A Life, by Martin Gilbert. The Guardian Weekly, 21 April 1991.

    http://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/80/buj9m/html [accessed on 26 June 2001].

    http://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/4/buk19/html [accessed on 26 June 2001].

    SBCCN: Saarbrucken Corpus of Conversational Narrative, about 23.000 words of spoken (American) English;

    public online access at http://www.uni-saarland.de/fak4/norrick.

    Barsalou, Lawrence, 1992. Cognitive psychology. An Overview for Cognitive Scientists, Lawrence Erlbaum,Hillsdale, NJ.

    Bransford John, D., 1979. Human Cognition Learning, Understanding and Remembering. Wadsworth Publishing,

    Belmont, California.

    Bransford John, D., Johnson Marcia, K., 1973. Considerations of some problems of comprehension. In: Chase,

    W.G. (Ed.), Visual Information Processing. Academic Press, New York/London, pp. 383438.

    Brown, Gillian, Yule, George, 1983. Discourse Analysis. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Bublitz, Wolfram, 1999. Introduction: views of coherence. In: Bublitz, W., et al. (Eds.), Coherence in Spoken and

    Written Discourse: How to Create It and How to Describe It. Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia, pp. 1 7.

    Bublitz, Wolfram, 2001. Why that now: some notes on cohesion and coherence [manuscript].

    Bublitz, Wolfram, Lenk, Uta, 1999. Disturbed coherence: fill me in. In: Bublitz, W. (Ed.), Coherence in Spoken

    and Written Discourse: How to Create It and How to Describe It. Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia, pp.

    153174.

    Bussmann, Hadumod, 1996. Routledge Dictionary of Language and Linguistics. Routledge, London.

    Chafe, Wallace, 1977. Creativity in verbalization and its implications for the nature of stored knowledge. In:

    Freedle, R.O. (Ed.), Discourse Production and Comprehension. Ablex, Norwood, NJ, pp. 4155.

    Channell, Joanna, 1994. Vague Language. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Clark Herbert, H., 1978. Inferring what is meant. In: Levelt, W., Flores d Arcais, G. (Eds.), Studies in the

    Perception of Language. Wiley, New York, pp. 295322.

    de Beaugrande, Robert, Dressler, Wolfgang, 1981. Introduction to Text Linguistics. Longman, London.

    Falkner, Wolfgang, 1997. Verstehen, Miverstehen und Miverstandnisse, Niemeyer, Tubingen.

    Fillmore Charles, J., 1975. An alternative to checklist theories of meaning. In: Proceedings of the First

    Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistic Society, Berkeley Linguistic Society, Berkeley, CA, pp. 123

    131.Fillmore Charles, J., 1977. Scenes-and-frames semantics. In: Zampolli, A. (Ed.), Linguistic Structures Processing.

    North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 5581.

    Fillmore Charles, J., 1982. Frame semantics. In: Yang, I. (Ed.), Linguistics in the Morning Calm. Selected Papers

    from SICOL-1981. Hanshin, Seoul, pp. 111137.

    Fillmore, Charles J., 1985. Frames and the semantics of understanding. Quaderni di Semantica 6, 222254.

    Fillmore, Charles J., 1986. U-semantics, second round. Quaderni di Semantica 7, 4958.

    Goffman, Erving, 1974. Frame Analysis. Northeastern University Press, Boston.

    Goffman, Erving, 1981. Forms of Talk. Basil Blackwell, Oxford.

    Grice, H.P., 1975. Logic and conversation. In: Cole, P., Morgan, J.L. (Eds.), Syntax and Semantics. Speech Acts,

    3. Academic Press, New York, pp. 4158.

    Halliday, M.A.K., Hasan, Ruqaiya, 1976. Cohesion in English. Longman, London/New York.

    Hoey, Michael, 1991. Patterns of Lexis in Text. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Konerding, Klaus-Peter, 1993. Frames und Lexikalisches Bedeutungswissen. Niemeyer, Tubingen.

    Levinson, Stephen, 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705704

    http://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/80/buj9m/htmlmhttp://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/4/buk19/htmlhttp://www.uni-saarland.de/fak4/norrickhttp://www.uni-saarland.de/fak4/norrickhttp://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/4/buk19/htmlhttp://uk.sports.yahoo.com/010609/80/buj9m/htmlm
  • 8/2/2019 Overzichtsartikel Framing

    21/21

    Minsky, Marvin, 1975. A framework for representing knowledge. In: Winston, P.H. (Ed.), The Psychology of

    Computer Vision. McGraw-Hill, New York, pp. 211277.

    Minsky, Marvin, 1977. Frame-system theory. In: Johnson-Laird, P., Wason, P.C. (Eds.), Thinking. Readings in

    Cognitive Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 355376.

    Muller, Klaus, 1984. Rahmenanalyse des Dialogs. Narr, Tubingen.

    Piaget, Jean, 1969. The Psychology of Intelligence. Littlefield Adams, Paterson, NJ.

    Quirk, Randolph, Greenbaum, Sidney, Leech, Geoffrey, Svartvik, Jan, 1973. A University Grammar of English.

    Longman, London.

    Quirk, Randolph, Greenbaum, Sidney, Leech, Geoffrey, Svartvik, Jan, 1985. A Comprehensive Grammar of the

    English Language. Longman, London.

    Raskin, V., 1984. Semantic Mechanisms of Humor. Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Sanford, Anthony, Garrod, Simon, 1981. Understanding Written Language. Wiley, Chichester.

    Schank, Roger C., Abelson, Robert, 1977. Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding: An Inquiry into Human

    Knowledge. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.

    Schwarz, Monika, 1997. Anaphern und ihre diversen Antezedenten: Koreferenz und Konsorten. In: Durscheid,

    C., Ramers, K.H., Schwarz, M. (Eds.), Sprache im Fokus. Festschrift fur Heinz Vater zum 65, Geburtstag,Niemeyer, Tubingen, pp. 445456.

    Shanon, Benny, 1981. Whats in the frame? Linguistic indicators. Journal of Pragmatics 5, 3544.

    Stubbs, Michael, 2001. On inference theories and code theories: corpus evidence for semantic schemas. Text 21/3,

    437465.

    Tannen, Deborah, 1993a. Introduction. In: Tannen, D. (Ed.), Framing in Discourse. Oxford University Press,

    Oxford, pp. 313.

    Tannen, Deborah, 1993b. Whats in a frame? Surface evidence for underlying expectations. In: Tannen, D. (Ed.),

    Framing in Discourse. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 1456.

    Tannen, Deborah, Wallat, Cynthia, 1993. Interactive frames and knowledge schemas in interaction: examples from

    a medical examination/interview. In: Tannen, D. (Ed.), Framing in Discourse. Oxford University Press,

    Oxford, pp. 5776.

    Thompson, Geoff, Zhou, Jianglin, 2000. Evaluation and organization in text: the structuring role of evaluativedisjuncts. In: Hunston, S., Thompson, G. (Eds.), Evaluation in Text: Authorial Stance and the Construction of

    Discourse. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 121141.

    Ungerer, Friedrich, Schmid, Hans-Jorg, 1996. An Introduction to Cognitive Linguistics. Longman, London.

    Vuchinich, Samuel, 1977. Elements of cohesion between turns in ordinary conversation. Semiotica 20, 229 257.

    Yule, George, 1996. Pragmatics. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Monika A. Bednarek is a doctoral candidate in linguistics at the University of Augsburg, Germany, with research

    interests in cognitive linguistics, pragmatics and text linguistics. Specific interests include cohesion and

    coherence, frames, and evaluation in the press. Her masters thesis was concerned with an assessment of the

    application of frames in linguistics.

    M.A. Bednarek / Journal of Pragmatics 37 (2005) 685705 705