Jeroen Temperman

download Jeroen Temperman

of 36

description

Joroen Temperman

Transcript of Jeroen Temperman

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    1/36

    Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2041256

    Forthcoming in: Jeroen Temperman (ed.), The Lautsi Papers: Multidisciplinary

    Reflections on Religious Symbols in the Public School Classroom (BRILL/Martinus

    Nijhoff Publishers, 2012).

    Religious Symbols in the Public School Classroom

    Jeroen Temperman*

    I. Of Symbols, State Education, and Relevant Human Rights QuestionsStates are under international human rights obligations to make available free and

    compulsory primary school education and to make generally available secondary

    educationaccess to such state education must be universally guaranteed. State

    education must be provided in an objective, critical and pluralistic manner, free fromreligious coercion or misplaced proselytism. This host of positive and negative

    obligations in the combined areas of public education, curriculum-building, and the

    protection of religious liberty may have different legal ramifications depending on the

    peculiarities of the case. Notably, situations where acts of the State adversely impact

    access to education and conscientious liberties of child or parent differ from instances

    where the acts of other individuals could affect access to education and religious

    freedoms, considering the fact that in the latter scenario different individuals typicallyhave competing human rights claims.

    What is most remarkable in the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR)

    symbols jurisprudence is that more often than not a number of decisive preliminary

    questions are not raised, let alone satisfactorily addressed. Who in symbols cases

    and the variety of scenarios imaginable thereincan be identified as rights holders,

    and how far do concomitant obligations on the part of the state as principal duty

    bearer stretch? Under what circumstances may State neutrality be considered a

    legitimate ground for limiting fundamental rights? And who is actually supposed to

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    2/36

    Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2041256

    be neutralaccording to human rights lawStates, buildings, the public square,civil

    servants, teachers, students, and/or pupils? When does a symbol interferewith the

    rights and freedoms of others or public order? And who is to prove that? Also, what

    are the exact standards of proof in symbols cases? Consequently, the increasingly

    pertinent question emerges if and to what extent (international) courts may interpret

    and explain the meaningof symbols. If symbols do not have monolithic meanings

    that can be grasped by judges, the question is what, then, could be seen as more

    objective points of departure leading and informing a sound human rights analysis.

    II. Of Applicable Rights, Including the Rights of OthersWhen individuals wear religious attire or display religious symbols in public schools,

    a number of (specific elements of) human rights provisions will or might be engaged.

    The state could decide to restrict this display or the state could tolerate it; in both

    scenarios human rights provisions will be triggered. Setting aside for the time being

    all questions of legitimacy, any restrictionfrom national prohibitions to local bans

    to more individualized sanctions1of the individual display of symbols inevitably

    amounts to minimally an interference with the freedom to practise a religion of

    belief (theforum externum). In this regard it is crucial to observe that the freedom to

    manifest a religion is granted in public or private.2Thus, in principle there is a right

    to observe ones religion, including through the display of religious symbols, at a

    public school. This means that a limit put thereon by the state requires a special

    justification. This holds true for individuals regardless of their capacitypupil,

    student, teacher, school principal, or caretaker (everyone has the right)albeit that

    the individuals capacity may play a role in the context of necessity tests and

    potential balancing exercises.3

    In addition to the rights of the symbol-displayer, there may be other rights at

    stake, notably other persons rightsthe rights of the symbol-viewerto freedom of

    and freedom from religion. The latter negative religious liberties are typically

    * Thanks to Malcolm Evans for his comments on a draft of this Chapter (usual caveats apply).1And regardless of whether the legal restriction may result in fines, expulsion from school, an official

    admonition to remove the symbol, or the dismissal of a non-compliant teacher, etc.2 Article 18, para. 1, of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A

    (XXI), 21 U.N. GAOR Supp. (No. 16) at 52, U.N. Doc. A/6316 (1966), 999 U.N.T.S. 171, of 16

    December 1966 [ICCPR]; and Article 9, para 1, of the [European] Convention for the Protection of

    Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, ETS No. 5, 213 U.N.T.S. 222, of 4 November 1950[ECHR or European Convention].3See section III, infra.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    3/36

    engaged, or triggered,4in the event that symbols are officially or de factotolerated by

    the state. With respect to these negative religious liberties, one may think, in the most

    extreme case, of religious coercion. The United Nations ICCPR makes this most

    explicit by providing that [n]o one shall be subject to coercion which would impair

    his freedom to have or to adopt a religion or belief of his choice. 5But also short of

    outright religious indoctrination, brainwashing or forced conversions, other policies or

    practices can be in breach of the ramifications of negative religious liberty. One may

    think of compulsory religious oaths schemes for entering public office.6 Certain

    optional religious oath schemes, too, are objectionable for reasons of negative

    religious freedom.7 Oath of office regulations that are premised on religious oaths

    being taken as a rule, whilst secular affirmations are regarded as the tolerated

    exception, could still lead to situation where one is forced to choose between

    revealing oneslack ofreligious belief or surrendering the dictates of ones

    conscience.

    Generally speaking, then, access to education rights and religious freedoms (of

    others) may be engaged inasmuch as individually displayed symbols may impose a

    conscientious obstacle to enrolling or remaining in those public schools where this

    display is permitted by the state. One may think of parents that have opted for the

    public school system precisely out of a (perceived) need for a religiously-neutral and

    symbol-free educational environment, thus nipping in the bud any peer pressure (vis-

    -vischild) or community pressure (vis--visparents and child) to observe religious

    dress codes.8

    Turning to state-imposed symbols in public schools, the most striking

    difference is that as far as the display of the symbol is concerned there is no clear

    rights holder here. The state or state schools as such do obviously not enjoy a rightto

    manifest a religion (under international law). What we face here is not necessarily an

    internationally guaranteed legal entitlement of the symbol-displayer, but an interestof

    the state and likely one of the religious majority; an interest to perpetuate a long-

    observed, precious tradition. It is doubtful whether we can deem this a collective

    4Again, we are not yet considering questions as to breaches of rights, solelyprima facieapplicability.

    5Article 18, para. 2, ICCPR.

    6Buscarini and Others v. San Marino, 18 February 1999, European Court of Human Rights, No.

    24645/94.

    7Alexandridis v. Greece, 21 February 2008, European Court of Human Rights, Appl. No. 19516/06.8Some of the ideas presented in relation to this pointsee alsosection III, infrahave benefited from

    on-going discussions on these matters with Professor Wibren van der Burg (usual caveats apply).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    4/36

    manifestationof belief within the ambit of the individual right to freedom of religion

    or belief. That individual right certainly has a collective dimension: the individual is

    also entitled to worship, teach, practice and observe a religion together with others.

    This recognition of collective manifestations of belief does indeed include a right of

    individuals and religious institutions to publicly display their religious symbols.

    However, this same recognition does not quite entail a clear-cut fundamental right of

    the dominant religion to place its symbols in all (state) buildings it sees fit. For the

    present purposes,9 what matters most is that the lack of a clear-cut human rights

    entitlement on the part of the symbol-displayer (the state) also means that conflicts of

    rights are not as evident here as they are in the area of individually-displayed symbols.

    Yet when we turn again to the flipside, the symbol-viewers (individuals), we must

    observe that that they remain entitled to a mix of fundamental religious and

    educational rights. Crucially, however, in this scenario of state-imposed symbolism

    we are not speaking of fundamental rights and freedoms of others, but of primary

    rights holders vis--vis the state. Thus, negative religious liberties and universal

    access to public education are engaged here not as potential limiting factors but as

    legal entitlements of primary rights holders.

    None of this implies that individuals displaying religious symbols ought

    always to win their cases, or that symbol-imposing statesacting for the religious

    majorityought to lose them as a matter of course or whenever challenged. However,

    these observations do impact on how religious symbols questions are to be framed

    within the human rights framework, especially when we take account of the special

    context that is provided bystate education.

    Applying these preliminary observations to the recent Lautsi case,10 the

    crucifix-in-public-school-classrooms case, the following is remarkable. First and

    foremost, the Grand Chamber does not spell out that this case is not evidently one of

    clashing religious rights. Quite the contrary, the Court accepts the position of the

    Italian Government which had argued that account should be taken of the fact that

    the Catholic religion was that of a large majority of Italians [T]he Court should

    9In this same section, infra, we will return to the question whether or not the religious majority has a

    legal entitlement to having religious symbols are displayed within public schools, or whether that

    interest falls short of a human rights entitlement.10

    Lautsi and Others v. Italy,18 March 2011, European Court of Human Rights (Grand Chamber), No.

    30814/06 (also referred to as the Grand Chamber decision). Lautsi v. Italy, 3 November 2009,European Court of Human Rights (Second Section), No. 30814/06 (further also referred to as the

    Chamber decision).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    5/36

    acknowledge and protect national traditions and the prevailing popular feeling11

    Just short of recognizing this as a right, the Grand Chamber sanctions Italysand all

    catholic Italians decision to perpetuate the crucifix tradition.12 Some of the

    concurring Judges reveal they do consider the case as a clear-cut clash of religious

    rights: the rights of non-believers and religious minorities versusand as outvoted

    bythe rights of all catholic Italians. Judges Rozakis and Vaji refer to aright of

    society, as reflected in the authoritiesmeasure in maintaining crucifixes on the walls

    of State schools, to manifest their (majority) religious beliefs.13 Accordingly, for

    these Judges this case boils down to one straightforward question: Does this right [of

    society] ... override the right of parents to educate their children in accordance with

    their religion and ... their philosophical convictions?14 Interestingly, and perhaps

    indicative of the tenability of the previous proposition, elsewhere these two Judges

    correct themselves when they refer to the right or interest of at least a very large

    segment of society to display religious symbols as a manifestation of religion.15

    Concurring Judge Bonello, too, literally balances the religious liberties of catholic

    Italians with the rights of minority believers (the Lautsis): If the parents of one pupil

    claim the right to have their child raised in the absence of a crucifix, the parents of the

    other twenty-nine should well be able to claim an equal right to its presence .16Judge

    Bonello elaborates on this point:

    All the parents of all the thirty pupils in an Italian classroom enjoy equally the fundamental

    Convention right to have their children receive teaching in conformity with their own

    religious and philosophical convictions, at least analogous to that of the Lautsi children.

    The parents of one pupil want that to be non-crucifix schooling, and the parents of theother twenty-nine, exercising their equally fundamental freedom of decision, want that

    schooling to be crucifixschooling. No one has so far suggested any reason why the willof the parents of one pupil should prevail, and that of the parents of the other twenty-nine

    pupils should founder. The parents of the twenty-nine have the fundamental right,

    equivalent in force and commensurate in intensity, to have their children receive teaching

    in conformity with their own religious and philosophical convictions, be they crucifix-friendly or merely crucifix-indifferent. Ms Lautsi cannot award herself a licence to overrule

    the right of all the other parents of all the other pupils in that classroom, who want to

    exercise the same right she has asked this Court to inhibit others from exercising.17

    If we follow that type of reasoning, we have to make an inventory in each and every

    public school classroom in Europe to discern what the majority religion isand if so

    11Lautsi and Others v.Italy, ibid., para. 37.

    12Ibid., para. 68.

    13 Concurring Opinion of Judge Rozakis, Joined by Judge Vaji, to Lautsi and Others v. Italy

    (emphasis added).

    14Idem.15

    Ibid., opening sentences (emphasis added).16

    Concurring Opinion Judge Bonello toLautsi and Others v. Italy, para. 3.6 (emphasis added).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    6/36

    desired by the latter, stick the triumphant symbol to the wall of that classroom. There

    are, however,18very plausible human rights claims and arguments why the parental

    liberties argument does not cut both ways. Collective positive freedom of religion

    does not include an unlimited entitlement for beneficiaries of that fundamental right to

    gear state institutions towards religions needs in any way the adherents of the

    majority religion see fit; whilst individual negative religious freedom guards against

    the threat of religious coercion, and has special significance in those areas where the

    state faces positive duties to make available socio-economic goods, such as education.

    The state is indeed under negative and positive obligations to make public school

    education available and universally accessible. Thus, it is in fact typically the case that

    the presence of a state-imposed symbol does, prima facie, engage religious and

    educational freedoms whilst the absence of state symbols does not, prima facie,

    engage those same freedoms.

    The best way to come to realize that point is to consider the reverse situation: a

    state that actually refuses to honour the majoritys wishes to display one particular

    religious symbol in all public school classrooms.19The refusing state does not through

    its actions engage the educational and religious rights of children and parents. Under

    international law the state is obliged to organize public school education freely

    accessible to all regardless of religious or non-religious affiliation;20the state is under

    no obligation to organizeand not even to fund21religiously-oriented education. In

    fact, with respect to the latter type of private education the obligations of the state are

    17Ibid., para. 3.5 (emphasis added).

    18As early as the Enlightenment and the French and American Revolutions, these reasons were, pace

    Judge Bonello, regularly suggested. If fact, these arguments were en vogue for such a long time, theymanage to find their way into the International Bill of Rights.19

    Or a state that would indeed remove all such already present symbols from public schools walls, thus

    ceasing a long-established tradition. Let us generally refer to these possibilities as the refusing state.20Article 28, paras. (a) (primary education) and (b) (secondary education), of the Convention on the

    Rights of the Child, G.A. res. 44/25, annex, 44 U.N. GAOR Supp. (No. 49) at 167, U.N. Doc. A/44/49,

    of 20 November 1989 [CRC or Childrens Rights Convention]. See alsoArticle 13, para. 2(a) (primaryeducation) and 2(b) (secondary education), of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and

    Cultural Rights, of 16 December 1966, G.A. Res. 2200 (XXI), U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., art. 26, U.N.

    Doc. A/6316 (1966), 993 U.N.T.S. 3 [ICESCR].21

    In relation to the creation of religious schools, church autonomy and the right to freedom of

    association naturally resists radical state interference: states may only insist on certain minimum

    standards pertaining to what subjects are included in the curriculum and pertaining to the desiredoverall quality (seesources in note23,infra, for details). The question whether it is right or wrong that

    the state is (permitted yet) not obliged to fund religious schools is an altogether different question and

    does not distract from the arguments presented here. It goes without saying that if the state should

    decide to fund private, denominational education, such funding must naturally be allocated in anequitable and egalitarian fashion. Cf. Human Rights Committee, Arieh Hollis Waldman v. Canada,

    Communication No. 694/1996, U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/67/D/694/1996, Views of 5 November 1999.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    7/36

    chiefly of a negative nature: a duty not to unduly interfere with private parties

    endeavours to provide for alternative schooling.22 These internationally codified

    residual rightsmake the fact all the more apparent that the refusing state in no way

    whatsoever interferes with religious or educational rights. For parents that do not wish

    to send their child to public schoolsthey may indeed very well have conscientious

    scruples over the fact that those schools are too public for their liking, i.e.

    deliberately pluralistic and not religion-minded in a confessional sensehave a right

    to opt for private, denominational schooling created outside the state educational

    system.23 Those same residual rights also guarantee crucifix schooling (as Judge

    Bonello puts it) or, for that matter, any other forms of confessional observance on the

    part of the school authorities that would not be appropriate within the public

    educational framework.24

    Thus, the Lautsi Grand Chamber decisions implicitand the concurring

    opinions explicitunderstanding that parental liberties mean within the public

    school context whatever the religious majority desires them to mean, is unsustainable

    from the perspective of international human rights standards. In what follows in this

    section (on childrens autonomous freedom of religion and educational rights), it

    becomes even more apparent how the ECtHR increasingly construes relevant

    Convention rights in ways that are incompatible with equivalent UN standards.

    The analysis so far has provided an overview of which rights may or may not

    be triggered by the different types of symbols cases. Further applying the inventory

    made to the Lautsi case, it is first of all remarkable how narrow a yardstick the

    ECtHR uses in its human rights analysis.25Notably, the Grand Chamber analyses the

    Lautsis claims exclusively in the light of Article 2 of Protocol I to the ECHR. On

    close reading the yardstick is even narrower than that: the Grand Chamber solely

    22 It may be repeated that some positive obligations can be discerned too; i.e., in relation to

    safeguarding minimal quality requirements.23

    International human rights law safeguards the possibility for the parents to opt-out of state schooling

    and send their child to private educational institutions. See, e.g., Article 13, paras. 3 en 4, of the

    ICESCR. See alsoArt. 5, para. 1(b), of the Convention Against Discrimination in Education, of 14

    December 1960, UNESCO, 11th Sess., 429 U.N.T.S. 93.24

    To be sure, the residual rights argument does not cut both ways either: everyone, including minority

    believers, must have access to genuine public schooling. It is the states obligationto provide that andthat alone. This means that minority believers or non-believers may not be expected to rely on a

    residual right to create sufficiently public schooling themselves in the event the state fails to do so.Put differently, a state that takes access of minorities to socio-economic goods seriously makes sure

    that the latter are guaranteed aprimary, not a residual right to that effect.25

    This section draws on Jeroen Temperman, Lautsi II: A Lesson in Burying Fundamental ChildrensRights, 6(3)Religion and Human RightsAn International Journal(2011), pp. 279283.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    8/36

    looks into the right of parents to ensure such education and teaching in conformity

    with their own religious and philosophical convictions (i.e., the second sentence of

    said provision). The right to education itself, mentioned in the first sentence of Article

    2 of Protocol I, remains largely unaddressed. Also, the Grand Chamber considers

    that no separate issue arisesunder the freedom of thought, conscience and religion,

    Article 9, of the Convention.26

    In relation toMs Lautsis claimspecifically, the Grand Chamber explains why

    it exclusively concentrates on the second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol I by

    postulating that parental liberties can be considered the lex specialis in the case at

    hand.27In the light of the system and wording of the European Convention this stands

    to reason: Ms Lautsi is above all concerned with ensuring that she can raise and

    educate her children in ways she sees fit, that is, according to the dictates of her

    conscience. Those concerns interact clearly strongly with her own conscience and

    beliefs, and her own religious liberties, though her freedom of religion or beliefper se

    may not be at stake in this case. The United Nations ICCPR, contrary to the

    European Convention, lists these parental liberties as an integral part of the freedom

    of religion clause,28 rather than as a part of the right to education clause, making a

    much stronger link possible between ones own religion, onesown religious liberties,

    and the related right to ensure that the education of ones children is in line with

    personal religious convictions. The European Convention system has opted for a

    slightly different approach by merging parental liberties with educational rights.

    Be that as it may, as far as the Lautsi childrenare concerned, who are separate

    applicants to the case,29there can be no question of lex specialishere, at least not for

    the full 100 per cent of their claims. The Lautsi children enjoy two fundamental rights

    here: a right to freedom of religion or belief and a right to (access to) public school

    education. This is the very reason they are individual applicants to the casethe

    rights and interests of the different applicants to this case do not fully coincide.

    Specifically, the relevant childrens rights are larger in scope than parental liberties.

    The European Courts automatic identification of parental liberties as the lex specialis

    in cases of freedom of religion that involve children is not at all self-evident if we

    look at the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child and the workings of the

    26Lautsi and Others v.Italy,supranote10,paras. 77 and 78.27

    Ibid., paras. 5960.28

    Art. 18, para. 4, ICCPR.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    9/36

    Committee on the Rights of the Child.30Taking the best interests of the childand

    the evolving capacities of the child seriously, circumstances can be such that

    childrens conscience and their interests in access to public school education engage

    autonomous rights. There obviously exists tension between parents liberties (to

    ensure the religious and moral education of their children in conformity with their

    own convictions)31and childrens autonomous right to freedom of religion or belief

    and their right to education.32 With the entry into force of the Childrens Rights

    Convention in 1990, at the global (UN) level the paradigm has shifted from always

    decisive parental rights to the recognition that childrens rights may function

    autonomously with parental rights being accessory. This holds true for situations

    revolving around legally non-mature children that de factoare mature enough to form

    an opinion and speak their mind.33 The Convention on the Rights of the Child

    provides that States Parties shall respect the rights and duties of the parents and,

    when applicable, legal guardians, to provide direction to the child in the exercise of

    his or her right [to freedom of religion or belief] in a manner consistent with the

    29

    Lautsi and Others v.Italy,supranote10,para. 1 (note also the title of the Grand Chamber case).30Cf.Jeroen Temperman, State Neutrality in Public School Education: An Analysis of the Interplay

    Between the Neutrality Principle, the Right to Adequate Education, Childrens Right to Freedom ofReligion or Belief, Parental Liberties, and the Position of Teachers, 32 Human Rights Quarterly(2010), pp. 869872. Article 3 of CRC provides: In all actions concerning children, whetherundertaken by public or private social welfare institutions, courts of law, administrative authorities or

    legislative bodies, the best interests of the child shall be a primary consideration (see alsoArticles 9,18, 20, 21, 37, and 40 on the childs best interest principle). SeeArticle 5 of CRC on the evolvingcapacities of the child doctrine. Importantly, the evolving capacities doctrine is once repeated by CRC

    to additionally underscore its importance in one particular areanot coincidentally, the article dealingwith the childs right to freedom of religion.31

    In addition to the second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol I to the ECHR, seeArt. 14, para. 2, of

    CRC; Art. 18, para. 4, ICCPR; Art. 13, para. 3, of ICESCR; Art. 5, paras. 1 and 2, of the Declaration on

    the Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and of Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief, adopted25 November 1981, G.A. Res. 36/55, U.N. GAOR, 36th Sess., U.N. Doc. A/RES/36/55 (1981).32

    Art. 14, para. 1, CRC states: States Parties shall respect the right of the child to freedom of thought,conscience and religion. SeeArt. 28 of CRC for childrens right to education. For a comprehensivestudy of childrens right to freedom of religion or belief as a right recognized by international law, seeSylvie Langlaude, The Right of the Child to Religious Freedom in International Law (Leiden: Martinus

    Nijhoff Publishers, 2007).33

    Cf. Eva Brems, Article 14: The Rights to Freedom of Thought, Conscience and Religion (A

    Commentary on the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child (Leiden/Boston: Martinus

    Nijhoff Publishers, 2006), p. 25. In this context it is worth emphasizing that the childrens right tofreedom of religion or belief as incorporated into CRC is of a later date than the ICCPR and CRC could

    be considered the lex specialis in this context. The ICCPR spoke of the liberty of parents and, whenapplicable, legal guardians to ensurethe religious and moral education of their children in conformity

    with their own convictions (emphasis added); whereas CRC mentions the rights and duties of theparents and, when applicable, legal guardians, to provide directionto the child in the exercise of his or

    her right in a manner consistent with the evolving capacities of the child (emphasis added).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    10/36

    evolving capacities of the child.34Parental guidance, in the words of Brems, has to

    recede as the childs capacities evolve.35 This means that when parents and child

    disagree about the desired form of education, under CRC standards it is anything but a

    foregone conclusion that parental liberties trump. This contrasts sharply with

    ECtHRs practice of deeming parental liberties automatically lex specialis in all

    freedom of religion cases that involve children.

    Take for instance the situation where parents want the child to take religious

    classes but the child does not, or vice versa. The Committee on the Rights of the

    Child, emphasizing the childs evolving capacities,36 expressed its concern in

    relation to Polish practice where students require parental consent to attend ethics

    courses.37Accordingly, the childsautonomous right to freedom of religion or belief

    could prevail in case of a conflict with the parents wishes, merited by the de facto

    maturity of the child. The same could be argued with respect to disagreements over

    larger issues such as the more general choice between denominational and non-

    denominational schoolingor the still larger questions as to belonging to a certain

    religion (or not). The Committee may not be in a position to fix in an absolute fashion

    the precise age when the child is empowered to make such decisions autonomously.

    However, from the fact that the Committee on the Rights of the Child requires (under

    the state reporting procedure)38information on the legal age for choosing a religion or

    attending religious school teaching it transpires that autonomous childrens rights are

    ideally granted some time before reaching legal majority.39All things considered, the

    precise moment indeed depends on the de factomaturity of the child, i.e.his or her

    ability to articulate a personal opinion on any of these matters. But once we decide to

    take that personally expressed opinion seriously, it in fact becomes the states duty, as

    Brems argues, to guard the limits of parental direction in matters of religion and

    34Art. 14, para. (2), of CRC (emphasis added); for a study on this parameter its legal relevance, seeG.

    Lansdown, The Evolving Capacities of the Child (Florence: UNICEF Innocenti Research Centre,

    2005).35

    Brems,supranote33,p. 26.36

    Ibid., para. 33.37

    CRC/C/15/Add.194 (2002), para. 32.38

    Committee on the Rights of the Child, General Guidelines for Periodic Reports(CRC/C/58, 1996),

    para. 24.39

    Cf. Brems, supra note 33,p. 30; she notes that some states have adopted legal provisions in that

    respect.E.g., Germany has stipulated that children can make these choices autonomously from age 14:Religious Education Act, RGBl S. 939, of 15 July 1921; while the Swiss Civil Code sets this age at 16

    years.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    11/36

    conscience, and if necessary to offer protection to children against infringement of

    their freedom of thought, conscience and religion by their parents.40

    In conclusion, in the light of the foregoing it is obscure why the Grand

    Chamber deems so uncritically that in relation to the Lautsi children, too, no separate

    issue arises under the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion. Children,

    the persons presently subjected to the practice we are discussing, may very well have

    an opinion and, what is more, some first-hand experience on crucifix schooling. In

    Lautsi, the second and third applicant were quite young at the material time; yet the

    point here is that by declaring parental liberties lex specialis from the outset and

    without any concrete reasons in the way of substantiation, the Grand Chamber never

    seriously entertained the possibility that children may have a bone to pick in this type

    of cases. Further, in theLautsicase both the Chamber and the Grand Chamber largely

    ignore the right to education per se.41 The Grand Chamber devotes precisely one

    paragraph to what it calls the case of the second and third applicants, which consists

    of no more than 4 sentences that are worth quoting in full:

    The Court considers that, when read as it should be in the light of Article 9 of the

    Convention and the second sentence of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1, the first sentence of

    that provision guarantees schoolchildren the right to education in a form which

    respects their right to believe or not to believe. It therefore understands why pupils who

    are in favour of secularism may see in the presence of crucifixes in the classrooms of

    the State school they attend an infringement of the rights they derive from thoseprovisions. However, it considers, for the reasons given in connection with its

    examination of the first applicants case, that there has been no violation of Article 2

    of Protocol No. 1 in respect of the second and third applicants. It further considers that

    no separate issue arises in the case under Article 9 of the Convention.42

    This paragraph in Lautsi is premised on rather serious errors. The reasons given in

    connection with its examination of the first applicant's casei.e. the reasons given

    why Ms Lautsis parental liberties were not infringedare nowhere near sufficient to

    establish that the Lautsi childrens religious and educational rights were not breached

    40Brems,supranote33,p. 29.

    41The near-exclusive focus on parental liberties is all the more remarkable as it transpires from the

    facts of the case that the second and third applicants, being the children, did indeed claim a violation of

    the right to education before the European Court. Lautsi and Others v. Italy, supranote10,para. 29

    provides (in part): The applicants complained of the fact that crucifixes were affixed to the wall in theclassrooms of the State school attended by the second and third applicants. They argued that this

    infringed the right to education, guaranteed by Article 2 of Protocol No. 1. The Chamber, in the firstLautsi decision, supra note 10, considered that both article 2 of Protocol I and article 9 of the

    Convention were relevant. When taken in conjunction and applied to the facts of the case, the

    Chambers Second Section held that the compulsory display of crucifixes does restrict the right of

    parents to educate their children in conformity with their convictions and the right of schoolchildren tobelieve or not believe. However, the right to education per se is addressed rather marginally.42Ibid., para. 78 (emphasis added).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    12/36

    either. Also, being in favour of secularism isindeednot what triggers religious

    and educational rights of those subjected to crucifix schooling, but the

    internationally codified agreements that oblige states to design a public school

    environment that is universally accessible and respective of minority beliefs. The

    upshot of the Grand Chambers approach is that childrens negative religious liberties

    and access to public education rights do not get serious attention; the same goes for

    access rights to socio-economic goods of minorities in general.

    III. Of Burdens and Standards of ProofA host of human rights norms is triggered by the public display of religious symbols.

    The circumstances of the casewho displays the symbol, who views the symbol, and

    within what specific settingfurther impact threshold and evidentiary matters,

    questions concerning the legitimacy of invoked grounds for restriction, questions as to

    the necessity and proportionality of interferences, the existence of a pressing

    social need, and relevant balancingexercises.

    In Lautsi, the Grand Chamber held that [t]here is no evidence before the

    Court that the display of a religious symbol on classroom walls may have an influence

    on pupils and so it cannot reasonably be asserted that it does or does not have an

    effect on young persons whose convictions are still in the process of being formed.43

    The well-known Dahlab v. Switzerland case dealt with the question whether the

    authorities were permitted to forbid Mrs Dahlab from wearing an Islamic headscarf

    whilst acting in her capacity as primary school teacher. Here the Court argued in

    relation to the potential effects of (these) religious symbols:

    The Court accepts that it is very difficult to assess the impact that a powerful external

    symbolsuch as the wearing of a headscarf may have on the freedom of conscience and

    religion of very young children. The applicants pupils were aged between four and eight,

    an age at which children wonder about many things and are also more easily influencedthan older pupils. In those circumstances, it cannot be denied outright that the wearing of

    a headscarf might have some kind of proselytising effect...44

    Accordingly, the European Court of Human Rights considers that in the absence of

    proof to the contrary in cases involving state display of symbols (notably, crucifixes)

    in public schools, it may be assumed that the symbol has no adverse effects on the

    rights of others; whereas in the absence of proof to the contrary in cases involving the

    43Ibid., para. 66.44

    Dahlab v. Switzerland, 15 February 2001, European Court of Human Rights, Appl. No. 42393/98, p.

    13 (emphasis added).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    13/36

    individual display of symbols (notably, Islamic headscarves) it may be assumed that

    the symbol does have adverse effects on pupils. From the perspective of individual

    human rights protection, these a priori assumptions are oddthey are much odder

    still if we consider the arbitrary premises on which the Court bases these

    presuppositions.

    It appears that the Courtsdecisions to fix the burdens and standards of proof

    the way it does is importantly premised on the concepts of essentially passive

    symbols (such as, in the eyes of the ECtHR, the crucifix) and powerful external

    symbols (such as, according to the ECtHR, the Islamic headscarf).45Much has been

    written on these characterizations, also in this volume.46Doubtless, those labels have

    triggered so much debate as they are rather arbitrary and odd in and for themselves.

    The Grand Chamber inLautsiwas right in concluding that the facts of the two cases

    [LautsiversusDahlab] are entirely different47however, both the reasons given for

    that conclusion and the consequences attached to it are wrong. From the Lautsi

    judgements context, it transpires that the crucifix is passivechiefly on account of it

    being on a wall.48 The crucifix is furthermore deemed passive as it cannot be

    deemed to have an influence on pupils comparable to that of didactic speech or

    participation in religious activities.49 These observations hardly serve as sound

    distinguishing factors: Mrs Dahlab did not use her headscarf as part of didactic

    speech or participation in religious activitiesshe was wearing one whilst teaching.

    Likewise, crucifixes were hanging on school walls whilst teaching took place.

    Considering the crucifix an essentiallypassivesymbol is plainly arbitrary and truly

    uninformed according to semioticians. Equally arbitrary is the presupposition that a

    crucifix on a wall cannot be deemed to have an influence on pupils, or that sign-

    language necessarily has less impact than didactic speech. Most if not all persons

    that observe the crucifix on a classroom wall will consciously or sub-consciously

    make the link between the signifier and the signified, that is, will match the symbol

    and the religion that is always/mostly/typically signified by it. What precisely happens

    in that continuous process of identification and re-identification may play out

    45Lautsi and Others v. Italy, supranote10,para. 72 (a crucifix on a wall is an essentially passive

    symbol).46

    Seeparticularly the Chapter by Andreescu & Andreescu, who identify three possible meanings of the

    passiveness of a symbol.47Lautsi and Others v.Italy,supranote10,para. 73.48

    Ibid., para. 72.49

    Idem.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    14/36

    differently for different personsyet in all instances that non-verbal sign-language is

    as active as can be. In fact, its activeness may become multiplied by the particular

    setting in which it takes place, in our casestate education, a compulsory setting where

    youths are also initiated in the basics of what is right and what is wrong. 50

    The ECtHR, however, does not cite any authority when it concludes that

    certain symbols are passive and others would be powerfulit seems to be basing

    itself purely on common sense. How common that sense really is becomes painfully

    evident when we reverse everything the European Court claims in this regard. A

    religious symbol on a wall of a state building is active, strong, powerful,

    external or political, etcetera, in so far as most if not all people perfectly

    understand it is the statethat has ordered or sanctioned it to be there, thus seemingly

    indicating a religious preference or at least attaching its seal of approval to what

    would typically be the dominant religion whilst refraining from bestowing any such

    seal of quality upon minority religions or non-religious faiths. Religious symbols or

    attire displayed by individuals, on the other hand, are passive, internal, weak,

    non-political, etcetera, in so far as most if not all peoplenotably those accustomed

    and content to live in a pluralist and tolerant societyperfectly understand that this

    symbol indicates a personal religious preference and, in the absence of concrete

    evidence to the contrary, no coercive attempt to impose on others that preference.

    From the perspective of parental liberties, the latter train of thought is certainly a very

    plausible one. How clear, scientifically speaking, any of those messages stemming

    from symbols in actual fact are to (young) children remains to be seen. 51The point

    here is that the Courtsa prioripresuppositions are shady at best given that they can

    so easily be reversedand come out stronger.

    All things considered, the ECtHR should not engage in its private common

    sense deconstructions of the meaning of symbols in the first place. A fortiori,

    international monitoring bodies should refrain from construing non-Western symbols

    as quintessentially illiberal since the Court is not qualified to make such assessments;

    and at any rate, there will always be sufficiently objectifiable factors present in

    symbol cases on which to base a critical and balanced human rights analysis. The best

    50Cf. Mawhinneys contribution to thisvolume. Seeher Chapter for a fascinating introduction into the

    discipline of semiotics.51

    Seetext around note69,infra, on the declining value of the teachers-as-role-models argument. Seealsoprevious note and particularly the contribution by Mawhinney in this book, on state symbols.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    15/36

    example of how this can go dreadfully wrong was in Dahlab, where the Strasbourg

    Court notoriously claimed that the headscarf:

    appears to be imposed on women by a precept which is laid down in the Koran and which

    is hard to square with the principle of gender equality. It therefore appears difficult toreconcile the wearing of an Islamic headscarf with the message of tolerance, respect for

    others and, above all, equality and non-discrimination that all teachers in a democratic

    society must convey to their pupils.52

    In Sahin, too, the wearing of Islamic headscarves is deemed synonymous with

    practices that are inherently coercive, necessarily reflect a degree of submission of

    women to men, thus affecting gender equality as a matter of course.53 This

    jurispathic role of courts is, as Brett Scharffs argues, to some extent inescapable

    and necessary. After all, the law as a normative institution is not just about creation,

    but preservation as well. A community that is exclusively creative, one that is in thegrip of competing jurisgenerative visions, will splinter and fall apart. The centre will

    not hold. One job of the judge is to decide among competing conceptions, even if it

    means eliminating others.54However, jurispathic judgeslike the European Court of

    Human Rights in the headscarf casesrisk overstepping the mark. Scharffs contends

    the following in particular reference to national (French) law and courts, but the

    argument very much applies to international monitoring bodies too:

    Judges, confronted with too much creativity in the elucidation of normative meanings by

    various communities within the polis, decide for one, put the coercive power of the state

    behind it, and in so doing destroy or attempt to destroy all other competing meanings. Thus,

    for example, when a legislature or court determines that the headscarf is a symbol ofoppression, its decision carries with it the coercive power of the state, and its determination

    of what the headscarf means is jurispathicit kills (or at least tries to), in a decisive andconclusive way, alternative meanings ... Muslim girls or women may have a different

    understanding of what the headscarf means, but when the state declares in an authoritative,

    official voice, those alternative meanings are not just undermined, they are delegitimized.55

    This basic understanding of what type of argumentscourts may accept at face value,

    and what type of arguments they may not, impacts evidentiary questions; notably, it

    will influence the burdens and standards of proof in symbols cases.

    Perhaps the ECtHR could have invited expert testimony critically elucidating

    the potential effects state or individually displayed symbols have on other people

    52Dahlab v. Switzerland,supra note44,p. 13.

    53Leyla Sahin v.Turkey, 10 November 2005, European Court of Human Rights, No. 44774/98, para.

    115 (seconding the Chambers considerations to that effect) and para. 116 (underscoring the equalitybefore the law of men and women).54

    Brett G. Scharffs, Four Views of the Citadel: The Consequential Distinction between Secularity andSecularism, 6:2Religion & Human Rights(2011), p. 124. See alsoScharffss Chapter on jurispathic

    versus jurisgenerative judicial interpretation in this book. 55Ibid., p. 123. In her dissenting opinon, Judge Tulkens argued and warned against too jurispathic an

    approach in Sahin. Dissenting Opinion of Judge Tulkens in Sahin, paras. 1112.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    16/36

    (from for instance semioticians, child pedagogy and child psychology experts in

    Dahlaband Lautsi).56When the government invokes grounds for restriction that are

    based on alleged proselytizing effects,such a reality checka moment to pause and

    reflect informed by expertswould not be out of the question. In relation to

    allegations of symbols inherent women-unfriendliness, or inherent illiberal

    significance, etc, it is more difficult to see how the ECtHR could invite sound expert

    testimony that would objectively explain the meaning of a symbol, for the plain and

    simple reason that there is no monolithic meaning of for instance the Islamic

    headscarf out there that could with absolute authority be graspednot even by

    experts. In cases like Sahin and Dahlab the Court could, however, relatively

    straightforwardly question if not falsify underlying Governmental assertions that a

    certain symbol doeshave one meaning and that this meaning is necessarily coercive.57

    That said, in symbols cases it is typically not actually necessary to invite

    expert data to settle these casesas long as we consider the proper mechanisms of

    human rights law and the derived equitable burdens and standards of proof. In the

    final analysis, the issue of proof of (the absence of) adverse effects is typically the

    states problem first and foremostnot the individuals. This holds true for cases

    involving state-imposed symbols as well as for cases revolving around restrictions of

    individually-displayed symbols. This point requires some closer inspection of these

    cases, linking questions of standards and burdens of proofs to our previous

    observations concerning applicable rightsas outlined in the previous section.

    In restriction cases such asDahlaband Sahin, at the outset of a legal analysis

    human rights law is in principle on the side of the symbol-displayer. The individual,

    be it a teacher, student or pupil, enjoys after all a fundamental right to manifest a

    religion both in public or private. Any state measure affecting this freedom

    minimally amounts to an interference with theforum externum.58The latter freedom is

    clearly not absolute, but the state will need to substantiate an overriding need to

    interfere with this freedom, citing accepted grounds for restriction. In symbols cases

    56Mawhinneys contribution to this volume is a case for a more multi-disciplinary approach to this type

    of cases, notably legal reasoning must incorporate insights from semiotics.57

    For instance, by giving a voice to the very women that have a stake in the case at hand. As Judge

    Tulkens argues, [w]hat is lacking in this debate is the opinion of women, both those who wear theheadscarf and those who choose not to. Dissenting Opinion of Judge Tulkens in Sahin,supranote55,

    para. 11.58

    In Dahlab, supra note 44, too, which concerns a teacher, dress rules amount at least to an

    interference according to the ECtHR (at pp. 1112 reference is repeatedly made to the interference).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    17/36

    potential legitimate grounds are the protection of the rights and freedoms of others

    and conceivably the protection of public orderor public safety.59If the symbol-

    displayer is an individual, and thus a primary human rights holder vis--visthe state, a

    purely theoretical need to interfere with fundamental rights can hardly ever be

    considered legitimateone would assume and hope. Such is however precisely what

    occurred in Dahlab. The fact that it cannot be denied outright that Islamic

    headscarves might have some kind of proselytising effect, as such, is far too

    abstract and vague a ground to be considered truly legitimate. Only by granting the

    state an excessively wide margin of appreciation, in one and the same act destroying

    the very core protection guaranteed by the fundamental right to freedom of religion,

    could this defence be accepted by the European Court. The Court in Dahlab in fact

    concedes there was no actual clash of rights, only an academic one. 60 It is true that

    mere threats to the rights of others may underexceptionalcircumstances justify

    interferences. However, in that case some minimum proof of that risk must be

    presented by the state. The state may be considered best positioned to make

    assessments as to certain threatsit is not denied that margins of appreciation do

    need to play a role here. Yet in order to prevent restrictions from being exclusively

    based on groundless fears, some minimal substantiation on the part of the state may

    be expected; moreover, the level of international supervision should minimally

    include the possibility to pronounce the absence of a pressing social need (to

    restrict) in the event a state does not present that minimal case.61

    Put differently, at this stage of our human rights analysis the onus to prove

    adverse effectsstill lies squarely on the state. It cannot reasonably be expected from

    the symbol-displayer, who in principle does nothing more than exercise a fundamental

    right, to prove that she does not abuse her right (at least, not as long as the state has

    not provided anything in the way of proof that such would be the case, i.e. some

    minimal case warranting a reversal of the burden of proof). Following that reasoning,

    59 Art. 9, para. 2, ECHR lists the accepted grounds for limitation. In Dahlab (ibid., p. 9) the

    Government argued that the aims pursued were undeniably legitimate and were among those listed inthe second paragraph of Article 9 of the Convention. In their submission, the measure prohibiting the

    applicant from wearing an Islamic headscarf was based on the principle of denominational neutrality inschools and, more broadly, on that of religious harmony. The Court reformulates (and accepts) theseaims as the protection of the rights and freedoms of others, public safety and public order ( ibid., p.11).

    60Ibid., p. 12 (potential interference).61 Cf., mutatis mutandis, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Malinverni Joined by Judge Kalaydjieva to

    Lautsi and Others v. Italy, para. 1.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    18/36

    it is all the more remarkable that the fact that the municipal school authorities in

    Dahlabhad not received a single complaint from parents in relation to her wearing a

    headscarf is nowhere considered to be a relevant factor by the ECtHR.62 After all,

    such facts are indicators or initial proof (i) that what we are dealing with is a normal

    exercise of a fundamental right and that abuse of rights allegations seem groundless;

    (ii) that rights-of-others and public order limitations advanced by the state prima

    facielack real weight (i.e., a pressing social needto restrict is lacking); and (iii) that

    the religious manifestation is in principle still covered by human rights law,

    requiring further substantiation from the state as to the necessity of the interference

    (i.e., in addition to we fear this individual display may harm others).

    None of this goes to show that it is completely out of the question that the

    restricting state wins a case against an individual symbol-displayer. The analysis so

    far solely reiterates what human rights protection of the freedom to manifest a religion

    is all about: when states restrict personal manifestations of religion, a substantiation of

    the necessity and proportionality of the invoked ground for limitation is required. If

    the aim invoked is the safeguarding of the rights of others, that substantiation may be

    expected to be particularly thorough if a clash of rights is not something evident.

    Specifically, if children/parents do not quite feel that their rights are at stake, the state

    may not seize their rights as an abstract ground for limiting individual religious

    manifestations. It cannot be ruled out, however, that the state successfully establishes

    that adverse effects on the rights of others are so imminent that state interference is

    warranted (or, alternatively, that this risk has been established to the extent that the

    burden of proof shifts to the symbol-displayer to dispel the information presented by

    the state). For instance, a state may be ableunlike Switzerland inDahlabto bring

    to the attention of the Court particular facts indicating that the display of the religious

    symbol is accompanied by active acts of improper proselytism on the part of the

    teacher.

    There are also circumstances imaginable that potentially warrant state

    interference with the manifestation of religion for reasons that go beyond those

    62Dahlab v. Switzerland,supra note44,p. 1: the schools inspector informed the Canton of Geneva

    Directorate General for Primary Education that the applicant regularly wore an Islamic headscarf at

    school; the inspector added that she had never had any comments from parents on the subject. Andibid., p. 4: In displaying a powerful religious attribute on the school premisesindeed, in the

    classroomthe appellant may have interfered with the religious beliefs of her pupils, other pupils at theschool and the pupils parents. Admittedly, there have been no complaints from parents or pupils todate(ECtHR quoting domestic proceedings).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    19/36

    pertaining to the individual behaviour of the symbol-displayer. As those external

    reasons, reasons beyond our own control, are naturally particularly difficult to

    stomach, we must tread very carefully here. It should be emphasized that any such

    reasonsif valid at allmust be construed very narrowly, must as a matter of

    principle be considered as temporary, and must very thoroughly be substantiated by

    the state. Let us consider the example where a public school receives complaints from

    parents that have concrete reason to fear their child may be pressured into accepting

    religious dress codes they themselves, parents and child, do not wish to observe.

    Under such circumstances, and if state or school authorities can prove concrete peer

    pressure(non-observing children are reproached by children of religious parents) as a

    part of wider patterns of general community pressure (many religious parents want

    their children to observe religious garb rules in a particular school, particular quarter

    of district or other well-defined locality), the introduction of temporary and targeted

    neutral dress rules may be said to serve a legitimate aim. It cannot be overemphasized

    that none of these factorsreligious demography, possibility of community or peer

    pressure, etceteraever justify sweeping national bans on the individual display of

    religious dress and symbols for the simple reason that such a measure is bound to fail

    the proportionality test. In all Western European states that have recently introduced

    such drasticdraconianbans lesser interfering measures were possible, namely a

    law authorizing the local authorities (school boards, municipal/borough

    administrations or other local administrative units) to adopt designatedand temporary

    measures to pacify recorded instancesof religious pressure.

    Also, the higher the form of education, the higher the standards of proof

    regarding the necessity of such measures may be expected to be. In this regard,

    mature university students, such as in Sahin,can be meaningfully distinguished from

    primary school children, such as in Dahlab.63Admittedly, that is a common sense

    distinction and deconstruction too. Yet this distinction does not boil down to

    venturing into the meanings of symbols per se, but rather reflects the internationally

    recognized acknowledgment that the less mature and empowered people are in cases

    of conflicting freedoms of conscience, the stronger the protection of these rights of

    othersmay be expected to be. International childrens rights discourse on the best

    interest of the child and the evolving capacities of the child are reasonably

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    20/36

    objectifiable criteria that in fact allow us to circumvent doctrinal debate about

    symbols per se.

    In addition to the protection of the rights and freedoms of others, the need to

    preserve the non-denominational character of the state and state schools (or more

    generally, the neutrality of the state;or more narrowly, the secularityof the state)

    is typically advanced by the state as a ground to interfere with the display of symbols

    in those symbols cases where individuals act as symbol-displayer.64State neutrality is

    a legitimate ground for limitation only insofar as it can be deemed a prerequisite for

    the protection of the rights of others and for public order.65This possible ground for

    interfering with the display of symbols begs the question what (acts, situations) could

    actually be said to affect the neutral character of the state or of the state school

    system specifically. In other words, who may be expected to be neutral? And to

    what extent? It is possible to distinguish teachers from the stateitself. Obviously the

    distinction between teachers and pupils/students is also significant in the present

    debate. Let us start with the latter point.

    Though certainly entering the public realmin abstracto, public school pupils

    do not represent the state in any way whatsoever inasmuch as they simply make use in

    a private capacity of a servicea compulsory one in case of primary school

    education66that is provided by the state. The same goes for university students,

    though they enter this public space on a more voluntary basis. It may be reiterated

    once more that freedom of religion or belief is in principle protected in public or

    private. Accordingly, in the absence of extreme circumstances (proven community

    and peer pressure, religious strife) it can hardly ever be considered necessary to

    altogether ban the display of individual religious symbols from the public school

    system for that system to be and remain non-denominational (or neutral, or

    secular). The display of religious symbols by individuals, if there are no concrete

    63To be sure, note that in Dahlab, ibid., neither religious pressure by the teacher nor community or

    peer pressure by parents or children to wear a headscarf was proven by the state.64

    E.g., inDahlab, ibid., p. 2 (the strict obligation of denominational neutrality), p. 4 (the principleof denominational neutrality).65

    InDahlab, ibid., p. 4, it was concluded during the domestic procedure that the impugned decision isfully in accordance with the principle of denominational neutrality in schools, a principle that seeks

    both to protect the religious beliefs of pupils and parents and to ensure religious harmony, which in

    some respects is still fragile. The European Court, ibid., p. 12, underscores several times (byimplication) the denominational neutrality of the public school system as a legitimate ground for

    restriction.66

    Secondary schooling is typically largely compulsory too, depending on national legislation on

    compulsory education and the fixed school-leaving age.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    21/36

    indicationsbeyond unsubstantiated fearsthat such display is accompanied by or

    triggers religious pressure, does not show the failure of state neutrality. If anything, it

    shows there is equal respect for the manifestations of different beliefs by individuals,

    also in public. To the extent that pupils/students can be said to affect the neutrality

    or secularity of the state non-verbally and inadvertently, such is in principle covered

    by their right to observe their religion in public. Consequently, the denominational

    neutrality card should not uncritically be accepted when played out against

    pupils/students.67

    With respect to public school teachers the situation is different inasmuch as

    the link between these individuals and the stateand the latters need to observe

    neutralityis a closer one.68 That arguably holds true regardless of the question

    whether or not public school teachers are appointed as civil servants under domestic

    law. On the face of it, then, that fact may lend some support to abstract

    argumentations premised on teachers-as-role-models in conjunction with the

    argument that public service workers expressly or implicitly wave some of their rights

    when they enter their function. Still, though, the neutrality argument in the present

    context should not be accepted as a wholesale justification. Despite the fact that some

    deference to the states position on any of this may be in order, not all abstract

    arguments should be uncritically accepted.

    First, note that the argument that teachers function as a role-model, and that

    especially younger pupils would be likely to copy the behaviour of this authoritative

    figure, does not find an equivalent in the relevant contemporary scientific research.69

    That observation casts serious doubt on the assumption that teachers attire and

    symbols as such(i.e., in the absence of express proselytizing behaviour) might have

    some kind of proselytising effect (i.e., the Dahlab formula). In the light of the

    foregoing discussion on the position of international judges, the question is whether

    international monitoring bodies should (by virtue of granting states a wide margin of

    appreciation) acquiesce in abstract proselytism arguments or whether instead critical

    inquiries into the exact necessity of the symbol/dress ban are in order. Considering the

    fact that we are dealing with a symbol-displayer as individual rights holder,

    international scrutiny is most certainly in order. If special proof of the risk of

    67See alsoDissenting Opinion of Judge Tulkens in the case of Leyla ahin v. Turkey,para. 5.

    68Cf. ibid., para. 7.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    22/36

    proselytism is required in order to decide the case, it is the state that faces the

    evidentiary burdenindividuals, also in their capacity of teachers, in principle

    exercise a fundamental right.

    That is, unless we should conclude that public service workers are deprived of

    certain rights or at least of the public dimensions thereof. That is precisely the gist of

    the related waver-of-rights argument: regardless of whether they are formally under

    the domestic laws considered civil servants or not, public school teachers work for a

    public institution, a position they have voluntarily taken up. In contrast to the position

    of pupils/students, one could accordingly considerthe argument goesthat teachers

    represent the state to some extent, and at any rate may be expected to abide by certain

    professional duties that come with working for a public institution.

    But abstract fears alone again ought not to be all-decisive at this specific

    junction of our symbols discussion. To a considerable extent, the public manifestation

    of religion by individualsthrough the use of symbols is only as problematic as states

    make it and want it to be. Certainly, there may be niches of the public square where

    strict denominational neutrality cannot be subject to any compromise (e.g., the

    impartial appearance of the judiciary); however, not all that is deemed public is

    necessarily or automatically adversely affected by the individual display of symbols.

    In some parts of Europe individually displayed symbols by for instance policemen is

    ever so unproblematic and has not led to public indignationimportantly because it is

    legally not treated as a problematic issue. This almost appears a self-enhancing

    principle: the less the state panics about the individual display of religious symbols in

    public places, even where it concerns public service workers, the more visibly and

    literally pluralistic and equally respective of symbols the state is and appears, and the

    more likely it is that the symbol-viewer, in turn, finds it rather normal that s/he is

    confronted with a personal religious symbol in the public space. Unfortunately, the

    flip-side seems to hold equally true:political and legislative panic may very well

    foster societal panic. Also note in this regard that the vehement and obstinate rejection

    of individual religious symbols from public spaces is very symbolic in its own right:

    religion as something for at home. And: only persons that show no sign of religion

    may be expected to serve the public well.

    69SeeStijn Smets contribution to this Volume, particularly section V of his Chapter and the there cited

    child psychological and pedagogical research.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    23/36

    Let us turn now to the altogether different situation where the state acts as

    symbol-displayer and where individuals are rights holders chiefly as symbol-viewers.

    None of the above goes to show that statesare free to display any symbol they see fit,

    anywhere they see fit. It may be reiterated that where the state acts as symbol-

    displayer we can hardly consider the state to qualify as rights holder under

    international human rights law. Human rights argumentswhich, alarmingly, can

    actually be found inLautsipremised on the a priori overruling force of perpetuating

    majority traditions are flimsy indeed.70 There is no such thing as a right of the

    dominant religion to display symbols inside the public premises of its choosing. That

    practice is a possibility, indeed a tradition,71but in line with what we have seen a

    rather objectionable one from the perspective of the requirements of freedom of

    religion or belief, equality before the law, and equal access to public services. The

    state that would downright refuse the display of symbols of the dominant religious

    tradition in public schools would not interfere with any fundamental right, a position

    further supported by the existence of residual religious and educational rights.72It is

    indeed precisely the existence of the right of churches, religious communities, and

    private school boards, to design alternative schooling with an expressly non-critical,

    deliberately non-objective, and distinct non-pluralistic teaching environment, that

    makes it all the more important for states to keep public school education truly public.

    Crucifix schooling is fully guaranteed by international law, but not inside state-run

    institutions. Proselytizing young, impressionable pupils is fully accepted by

    international law, but non-state entities will have to organize that for themselves.

    Mindful of those preliminaries, let us further consider the position of the

    display-viewer, the latters fundamental rights and especially the derived equitable

    burdens and standards of proof in cases where the state imposes the symbol or

    sanctions the perpetuation thereof. The Grand Chamber in Lautsi applies as key

    yardstick the question as to whether the crucifix indoctrinates pupils.73There are two

    issues here: (i) whether that is an adequate human rights test in this case?; and (ii),

    once we have established the right test, who is to prove/falsify any adverse influence?

    70See supra, text at notes723.

    71 In the words of both the Italian Government and the Grand Chamber, Lautsi and Others v. Italy,

    supranote10,resp. paras. 3637 and paras. 6768.72See supra, text at notes723.

    73Lautsi and Others v.Italy,supranote10,para. 62.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    24/36

    The very narrow indoctrination test the Grand Chamber (chiefly) applies can

    be criticized for various reasons. First and foremost, this test departs from the

    comprehensive pluralism in education and non-proselytism tests formulated and

    applied by the Court in public education cases. From for instance Folger it follows

    that the public school framework and curriculum must be designed in a way so that it

    can be guaranteed that children are taught in an objective, critical and pluralistic

    manner.74The fact that the state has not expressly pursued an aim of indoctrination

    does not quite ensure that public school education is sufficiently pluralistic or

    universally accessible. As the Court postulated inFolger, abuses can occur as to the

    manner in which the [educational legislations] provisions in force are applied by a

    given school or teacher and the competent authorities have a duty to take the utmost

    care to see to it that parents religious and philosophical convictions are not

    disregarded at this level by carelessness, lack of judgment or misplaced

    proselytism.75For sure, the high-threshold question as to whether outright coercion

    takes place is certainly one of the most pertinent questions when we are dealing with

    cases where individualsdisplay symbols and where other individuals simultaneously

    hold rights as symbol-viewers. In those cases we need to know more or less precisely

    the adverse effects to know how to justly balance competing fundamental rights

    claims. Put differently, to restrict the individual display of religious symbols a degree

    of abuseof religious rights must be substantiated: it must become evident that we are

    dealing with an extraordinary case in which the individual indeed seeks to

    indoctrinate others or indeed minimally engages in so-called improper acts of

    proselytism.76 The position (superior, teacher, etc) of the symbol-displayer may

    certainly be taken into account so as to judge the latter; however, the fact in itself that

    a person decides to display a religious symbol does not amount to a clear aim of

    improper proselytism (for it is covered by a human right to behave in that way). In

    74Cf. Mawhinneys and Pieriks contributions to this volume (seesection III of Mawhinneys Chapter;

    and see section III of Pieriks Chapter). E.g. in Folger and Others v. Norway, 14 February 2006,European Court of Human Rights, No. 15472/02, paras. 84102.75

    Folger, ibid., para. 84(i) (emphasis added).76

    Whereas the ECtHR speaks of misplaced proselytism (Folger, idem;see also Hasan and EylemZengin v. Turkey, 9 October 2007, European Court of Human Rights, No. 1448/04, para. 52) or

    unrestrained proselytism (efika Kse and 93 Others v. Turkey. 24 January 2006, European Court ofHuman Rights, No. 26625/02) in relation to state obligationsin the area of public schooling; in relation

    to horizontal individual acts, the decisive factor is the properness of proselytism. Cf. Kokkinakisv.

    Greece, 25 May 1993, European Court of Human Rights, No. 14307/88, paras. 4849 (improperproselytism); andLarissis and others v.Greece, 24 February 1988, European Court of Human Rights,Nos. 23372/94; 26377/94; 26378/94, para. 45 (improper proselytism).

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    25/36

    short, we need to assess the actual behaviour of the symbol-displayer in order to make

    up the final balance. In the case ofstate-imposed symbols misplaced proselytismis

    rather easily prima facieestablished, for most if not all proselytizing endeavours on

    the part of the stateare misplaced. What would in the civilian worldespecially in a

    pluralistic and tolerant world where one is perfectly accustomed to diversitybe seen

    as an innocuous exchange of ideas which the recipient is free to accept or reject, may,

    within the confines of compulsory public schooling, be viewed as a form of undue

    pressure in abuse of power.77

    In addition to the outlined negative religious liberties, in those cases where the

    state imposes the symbol, and where the symbol-viewer is consequently the principal

    rights holder, important questions emerge regarding equalaccess to public services.

    Thus, our next question is whether the state may present parents/children with

    conscientious dilemmas in the area of the compulsory public good that is primary

    school education. Specifically, the dilemma is a forced choice between surrendering

    access to state education or surrendering ones (non-)religious conscience.78 Judge

    Bonello finds it absurd that anyone could, on grounds of religious liberty, find issue

    with a crucifix in a schoolroom.79 But perhaps it is not quite so unimaginable or

    unreasonable that parents that send their child to such a public school are very

    anxious that the state favours the predominant religionfavours it to the extent that

    the state goes out of its way ensuring an official salute to this religion in each and

    every state schooland that this very fact alone objectively, rather than subjectively,80

    undermines the public quality of state schools their children, and they themselves on

    account of their parental liberties, are entitled to.81

    77This is the Larissis formula (ibid., there employed to contrast the civilian world with the confined

    and hierarchical world of the military), here applied to compare the civilian world with areas where

    states exercise public authority. Again, this is not to say that all civilian display of symbols isnecessarily innocuous: how free others in the civilian world are exactly to accept or reject woulddepend on the context, and particularly on the behaviour of the symbol-displayer.78

    The fact that this is a real issue and not an academic one, and also that it is experienced beyond the

    realm of predominantly Catholic states, is reported by, e.g., Charles Russo in relation to Republika

    rpska. If religious (in this case Christian Orthodox) symbols are present in each and every publicschool throughout the state, children of non-believers or those belonging to minority religions may not

    have genuine access to public school education. Charles J. Russo, Religion and Education in Bosnia:Integration Not Segregation?, 3Brigham Young University Law Review(2000), p. 945.79

    Concurring Opinion Judge Bonello toLautsi and Others v. Italy, paras. 2.82.9.80

    The Grand Chamber held in Lautsi that the applicants subjective perception is not in itselfsufficient to establish a breach of Article 2 of Protocol No. 1 (Lautsi and Others v.Italy, supranote10,para. 66).

    81Needless to say, here residual rights of parents (in this case the rights of the non-religious to arrangeprivate education) do not remedy the situation: it is the states dutyunder international law to make

    available public education with adequate curricula, teaching methods, and to ensure universal access to

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    26/36

    In the event that Italy had adopted a law requiring all public schools to

    henceforth display a symbol representingequally unambiguously82atheism in

    each and every public school classroom, a breach of the Convention could be

    established likewise. Indeed, one wonders what the third party interveners reactions

    would have been should the Strasbourg Court, for instance, have condemned the

    Czech Republica somewhat more likely example with >50 per cent of the

    population consisting of atheists, agnostics, non-believers or no-organized believers

    on account of a federal law requiring that on each and every state school wall an A

    (for Atheism) be painted (or any other well-known atheist sign).83

    A state that imposes a crucifix in a public school classroom suggests that the

    religion that is thereby symbolized is the exemplary religion. A state that paints an

    Atheism sign on each and every public classroom wall suggests that pupils are well-

    advised to denounce all religion. Such state-imposed symbolism interferes with the

    right to freedom of thought, conscience or religion of parents and childreneven if

    the atheistic or religious majority share a heartfelt wish to perpetuate that tradition.

    And in eitherscenario there may very well be parents that cannot enrol their child in

    any such public schoolwithout doing serious harm to their conscience. Note that we

    are talking about (relatively) unambiguous religious symbols (e.g., a crucifix) and

    equally (relatively) unambiguous atheist signs (e.g., said A-signs). False analogies

    demonstrating84the innocuous nature of imposing on all the symbol of the dominant

    religion are easily made. The fact that we also see many secular symbols in the

    public square is quite beside the point. Also, comparing crucifix schooling with

    widespread forms of religious symbolism practised more generally in other areas

    (e.g., on flags or coats-of-arms) does not distract from sincere access issues in relation

    to public education caused by the former practice.

    Thus, in the area of state symbols the risk for actual indoctrination is only one

    concern. The states obligation to ensure that everyone can enrol in public schools

    state-organized education, which includes avoiding policies that could cause conscientious obstacles to

    universal access and enrolment.82

    E.g.the different variations on the A-symbol. See.

    Or think of the different No Religion symbols: i.e.a cross, the word God, or the word religionplaced against the background of a prohibited-sign. The A-symbol is most apt for the purposes of the

    analogy drawn here with religious symbols. No Religion symbols are overly anti-religious, ratherthan positively representing a non-religious (atheism, agnosticism, etc) faith.

    83Seeprevious footnote. To be sure, the Czech Republic has adopted no such ludicrous policy.84

    One is invited to consult the third party interventions inLautsifor some examples (Lautsi and Others

    v.Italy,supranote10).

    http://www.religioustolerance.org/atheist6.htmhttp://www.religioustolerance.org/atheist6.htm
  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    27/36

    without conscientious trouble is as important. It is odd why the European Court of

    Human Rights has not quite recognized this concern in relation to public education, as

    it has elaborated on this requirement in other areas of law and policy-making.

    Religious oaths of officea widespread tradition too in Europe and elsewhere85

    are not problematic because of a scientifically proven risk that the oath-taker will

    subsequently be a devout adherent to the dominant religion, but mainly because such

    oath schemes signal that normally the incumbent office holder adheres to the

    dominant religion. This is precisely the reason that even certain optional religious

    oaths schemes (if the religious oath is the rule and the secular affirmation the tolerated

    exception) are objectionable from a human rights perspective: the assumption is that

    normal office holders adhere to the religion or God sworn to. Moreover, non-

    believers or members of minority religions are forced to reveal that they do not share

    that dominant faith if they want to take the secular affirmationor alternatively feign

    the religious oath contrary to their conscience.86By and large the same goes for public

    education (and many other public services for that matter): even short of establishing

    the precise decree of indoctrination the conclusion must be that there is no place for

    religious symbols on walls of state school premises. There the main concern is that

    parents/children may reasonably think the state takes sides in religious mattersthe

    message is: the normal religion in this class is x. Even if that is not officially the

    intended message, and even if the state otherwise formally promotes pluralism, it is in

    this situation that it cannot be denied outrightto use the Dahlab formulathat

    ostensible religious preferences on the part of the state may impact every day school

    life.

    Consequently, parents objecting to the symbols presence in their childrens

    public school have aprima faciehuman rights case. Accordingly, the onus must be on

    the state to substantiate what measures it has taken to make absolutely sure that the

    symbol policy does notnegatively affect public education. It is quite remarkable that

    the fact that no evidencewas brought before the Court87on the symbol policys

    effects in Lautsi is held against the applicant. The nature of the Italian policy means

    that all public schools are obliged to display the crucifix with no possible local

    85Jeroen Temperman, StateReligion Relationships and Human Rights Law (Leiden/Boston: Martinus

    Nijhoff Publishers, 2010), pp. 316320.86Cf.Alexandridis v. Greece,supranote7;andBuscarini and Others v. San Marino,supranote6,forexamples of respectively optional and compulsory religious oath of office schemes.87

    Lautsi and Others v.Italy,supranote10,para. 66.

  • 5/26/2018 Jeroen Temperman

    28/36

    exceptions or opt-outs. Somewhat different is the situation where the display is in

    principle prescribed by national or local regulations, but where schools must remove

    the symbols in case of complaints by parentsa decent attempt at treaty-conform

    interpretation found in some of the jurisprudence stemming from constitutional,

    supreme or other courts in Europe (notably Spain).88What remains problematic in that

    situation, however, is that adherents of minority beliefs or non-believers are forced to

    reveal that they do not share the dominant religion and that they in fact find issue with

    a tradition cherished by the majority. The risk for ostracization or other repercussions

    alone could make affected persons decide to rather surrender their conscience and not

    speak out. The public space is created by the liberal state as a universally accessible

    domain precisely with a view towards guaranteeing that the state itself will neverbe

    it deliberately or inadvertentlyforce such dilemmas on any of its inhabitants.

    Here the analogy with opt-outs to religious instruction in public schools is

    quite apt. There is increasing evidence available that opt-out provisions are the

    problem rather than the solution (to the compulsion element of religious instruction in

    public schools).89The traditional view, formulated by most international monitoring

    bodies, including the UN Human Rights Committee and the ECtHR,90is that there are

    two main ways for the state to fulfil its relevant human rights obligations. It either

    creates an educational system and a public school curriculum in a designedly

    pluralistic manner. Or, alternatively, in case it does allow confessional religious

    instruction (i.e., religious education going beyond neutral courses about religions) in

    public schools, the state lives up to its commitments if it grants adequate opt-out

    rights.91However, if we consider the every-day reality of school-life and the practical

    88For more examples of how domestic courts have pacified state symbols questions, see the detailed

    country studies in the comparative part of this volume.89

    Alison Mawhinney et al, Opting Out of Religious Education: The Views of Young People fromMinority Belief Backgrounds (Belfast: Queens University Belfast, 2010); Yuko Chiba and AlisonMawhinney, Religious Education, Opt-Outs and Freedom of Religion in Schools, in Welfare of theChild and Beliefs of the Parents (Cyprus: University of Nicosia Press, 2010); Alison Mawhinney,

    Submission to the Human Rights Committee with Respect to the Third Periodic Report of Ireland

    [NGO Information], March 2008 (this shadow report is a response to U.N.